THE PROBLEM OF IRRESPONSIBLE PARTY GOVERNMENT

THE PROBLEM OF IRRESPONSIBLE PARTY GOVERNMENT

Introduction

American party politics may be as nationally competitive as they have ever been, but at the same time they are perhaps as unresponsive to aver­age citizens as they have been in a long time. It is this paradox that Professor Tabatha Abu El-Haj creatively interrogates in her essay, Networking the Party: First Amendment Rights and the Pursuit of Responsive Party Government. 1 Tabatha Abu El-Haj, Networking the Party: First Amendment Rights and the Pursuit of Responsive Party Government, 118 Colum. L. Rev. 1225 (2018).

Of course, the major political parties are the subject of constant aca­demic criticism these days, but Professor Abu El-Haj’s critique of today’s parties is distinctive. Contemporary criticism of the parties largely targets what most see as the excessive partisanship running rampant in American politics. This “hyperpartisanship” spills off many ugly byprod­ucts, including legislative gridlock, democratic unresponsiveness, and toxic antipathy among partisans. 2 See Michael S. Kang, Gerrymandering and the Constitutional Norm Against Government Partisanship, 116 Mich. L. Rev. 351, 411–18 (describing hyperpartisanship’s negative consequences). Professor Abu El-Haj recognizes all these symptoms of hyperpartisanship, 3 See Abu El-Haj, supra note 1, at 1226–27 (listing the ways the “United States is failing to live up to its intended democratic function”). but unlike most critics she identi­fies and focuses on the parties’ withdrawal from traditional associational politics as the most noteworthy cause. 4 See id. at 1231 (arguing that “reforming political parties as associations” is the way to solve the current political crisis). The parties, as Professor Abu El-Haj describes, have increasingly become elite-directed, campaign finance–focused vehicles driven overwhelmingly by ideological missions. 5 See id. at 1230 (“To the extent there is accountability today, it is almost entirely to party donors and ideological groups.”). What have gradually faded from party politics are thick social networks that once undergirded the major parties, in which “volunteers, rather than donors, take the lead.” 6 Id. at 1269. The consequence, in Professor Abu El-Haj’s view, has been that the parties spun off toward the ideological extremes, unmoored from the practical concerns and centrism of regular people who used to constitute the heart of both parties. 7 See id. at 1230 (describing how the major political parties are currently polarized and largely unaccountable to the electorate).

This Response considers Professor Abu El-Haj’s diagnosis of today’s party politics and her proposals for using First Amendment law to pro­mote what she calls the “associational-party perspective.” 8 Id. at 1233. In Part I, I describe Professor Abu El-Haj’s indictment of the traditional “responsi­ble party government” model and her proposed new doctrinal approach to “sustain and build partisan networks more capable of producing demo­cratic responsiveness and accountability.” 9 Id. at 1235. Part II evaluates the effi­cacy of her proposed solutions.

I. Responsible Party Government and the Associational Party

A. The Failure of Responsible Party Government

Professor Abu El-Haj’s principal worry is irresponsible party govern­ment: the chronic nonresponsiveness of the major parties to majority opinion in today’s American politics. She—along with Professors Ganesh Sitaraman, Bertrall Ross, Nick Stephanopoulos, and Kate Andrias, among others—introduces to legal scholarship the persuasive wealth of political science research demonstrating that the American political system no longer represents the preferences of average Americans. 10 See Kate Andrias, Separations of Wealth: Inequality and the Erosion of Checks and Balances, 18 U. Pa. J. Const. L. 419, 421 (2015) (“If we want to understand our cur­rent predicament . . . we need to focus not only on partisanship but also on the problems of concentrated wealth and its organization to achieve political ends.”); Bertrall L. Ross II & Su Li, Measuring Political Power: Suspect Class Determinations and the Poor, 104 Calif. L. Rev. 323, 329 (2016) (using empirical research to demonstrate that the Supreme Court’s suspect class jurisprudence has relied on flawed assumptions about political power in the United States); Ganesh Sitaraman, The Puzzling Absence of Economic Power in Constitutional Theory, 101 Cornell L. Rev. 1445, 1448 (2016) (“In a battery of studies over the last decade, political scientists have confirmed populist suspicions and demonstrated that economic elites dominate the American political system.”); Nicholas O. Stephanopoulos, Political Powerlessness, 90 N.Y.U. L. Rev. 1527, 1534–35 (2015) (describ­ing empirical analyses used to better measure political powerlessness in order to improve suspect class jurisprudence); Bertrall L. Ross II & Terry Smith, Minimum Responsiveness and the Political Exclusion of the Poor, Law & Contemp. Probs., Fall 2009, at 197, 199 (“[I]n the American two-party competition model, both parties have incentives to appeal to median-swing voters at the expense of marginalized group interests.”). This work confirms popular suspi­cions that the parties have been captured by a wealthy donor class from both ends of the ideological spectrum. 11 See Larry M. Bartels, Unequal Democracy: The Political Economy of the New Gilded Age 2 (2008) (“[T]he political process has evolved in ways that seem likely to rein­force the advantages of wealth.”); Martin Gilens, Affluence and Influence: Economic Inequality and Political Power in America 1–2 (2012) (“Th[e] ideal of political equality is perhaps impossible to fully achieve in the face of economic inequality . . . . [U]nder most circumstances, the preferences of the vast majority of Americans appear to have essentially no impact on which policies the government does or doesn’t adopt.”); Jacob S. Hacker & Paul Pierson, Winner-Take-All Politics: How Washington Made the Rich Richer—and Turned Its Back on the Middle Class 8 (2010) (describing how both major political parties cater to “America’s superrich”). However, Professor Abu El-Haj presents the overarching problem with a different emphasis and norma­tive direction, as she focuses on the dysfunction of the major parties. 12 See Abu El-Haj, supra note 1, at 1243–45 (describing how the political system has failed to “tether government officials to the preferences of their constituents” and pro­duced parties that are “remarkably ineffective at governing”).

Election law scholars and other legal commentators have criticized today’s hyperpartisanship for years now, but Professor Abu El-Haj is less concerned about hyperpartisanship than with the concomitant “hollow­ing out” of the parties. The major parties have disassociated from their rank-and-file membership and are increasingly dominated by social and economic elites motivated largely by intense ideological preferences. 13 See supra note 11 and accompanying text. As she explains, “Social insularity of party elites along with the unrep­resentative­ness of both voters and party activists affects the types of policies and actions that are considered, even in the absence of corrup­tion or undue influence.” 14 Abu El-Haj, supra note 1, at 1267. The parties, in her view, have polarized because they no longer respond to regular Americans and instead have been pulled to the ideological extremes by wealthy campaign contribu­tors and activist elites. “Donors and ideological partisans,” as she puts it, “have become the target audience for party brands, and concern for the preferences of the general electorate is largely coincidental.” 15 Id. at 1252.

An irony, Professor Abu El-Haj points out, is that our modern parties are exactly what constitutional law and political science have prescribed for effective democracy. 16 See id. at 1229–30 (“[T]he debate in legal-academic and policy circles has been driven by fidelity to responsible party government despite its well-documented failures . . . .”). A 1950 American Political Science Association (APSA) report on the political parties, issued by the era’s leading polit­ical scientists, proposed a theory of responsible party government that was eventually embraced by courts and constitutional law. 17 See id. at 1237. The APSA report reasoned that the parties should be ideologically well differenti­ated and firmly controlled by party leaders who would then offer voters a distinct choice between party nominees on election day. 18 See id. The parties would therefore cultivate clear ideological brands that would enable voters to match their own preferences and assign retrospective account­ability for policy outcomes. Voters, who consistently display only a modest interest and sophistication about politics, could better effectuate their preferences through elections if only the parties were ideologically dis­tinct and their political brands clearly defined. 19 See id. at 1238 (describing the responsible party government theory developed in the 1950 APSA report).

The emphasis on ideologically distinctive parties made sense at the time. The major parties during the postwar period were notoriously ambigu­ous, with enormous ideological overlap that made it difficult to characterize one party as more liberal or conservative than the other. 20 See Hahrie Han & David W. Brady, A Delayed Return to Historical Norms: Congressional Party Polarization After the Second World War, 37 Brit. J. Pol. Sci. 505, 509–12 (2007) (describing “an unprecedented level of overlapping voting [among Republicans and Democrats] in both the House and the Senate in the years immediately after the Second World War”). Neither party presented a coherent ideology or even a reasonably well-defined package of policy positions. 21 See id. at 512–16 (“During the 1950s, the distinctions between [the] parties on key national issues like race and the role of government were not so clear.”). Jim Crow Dixiecrats dominated the one-party Democratic South but were more conservative than their Democratic and Republican counterparts to the North. 22 See id. at 517 (explaining how Southern Democrats were pulled in a conservative direction by their districts even as the national party was becoming more liberal). Northeastern Republicans represented more liberal Yankee constituencies that were far more progressive than Southern Democrats on race and foreign pol­icy. 23 See id. at 515 (“[V]oters with liberal views on [race] issues continued to vote for Republicans (and vice versa) even beyond the 1960s.”). Both parties were thus a muddle, riven internally by ideological and regional disagreements, a patchwork of local parties that sorted out their differences mainly during national elections.

Over time, though, the major parties changed considerably. The Civil Rights movement of the 1960s produced the Voting Rights Act and began the ideological realignment of both parties. 24 See Richard H. Pildes, Romanticizing Democracy, Political Fragmentation, and the Decline of American Government, 124 Yale L.J. 804, 819–20 (2014) (describing how the Civil Rights era, and in particular the Voting Rights Act, “launched into motion” forces that would sort and polarize the Democratic and Republican parties). The Democrats slowly became the party of ideological liberals and Republicans the party of ideological conservatives. 25 See id. Southern Democrats defected to the Republican Party. 26 See id. Northeastern liberals gradually shifted from the Republican to the Democratic Party. 27 See id. By the 1990s, the parties became ideologically cohesive without the internal tensions of the midcentury. 28 See id. See generally Matthew Levendusky, The Partisan Sort: How Liberals Became Democrats and Conservatives Became Republicans 1–11 (2009) (describing the mechanisms through which voters have sorted between the two major parties along ideologi­cal lines).

The result is that the major parties now represent the ideological differentia­tion and partisan polarization that the APSA report urged in 1950. 29 See Morris P. Fiorina, Parties, Participation, and Representation in America: Old Theories Face New Realities, in Political Science: The State of the Discipline 511, 521–23 (Ira Katznelson & Helen V. Milner eds., 2002) (“[T]hose who read [the APSA report] typically report a response of the following sort: ‘Gee, a lot of what those guys wanted actu­ally has happened.’”). According to Professor Abu El-Haj, this is a shame. She argues that the APSA recommendations on responsible party government have been largely achieved but have not yielded the promised benefits for demo­cratic government. 30 See Abu El-Haj, supra note 1, at 1243 (“[T]he Democratic and Republican par­ties today are closer than ever before to the ideal called for by the APSA Committee on Political Parties. Yet, responsible party government has not emerged.” (footnote omitted)). As Professors Jacob Hacker and Paul Pierson quip, the APSA committee coveted responsible party government but “[w]hat they got—along with the rest of us—was irresponsible party govern­ment.” 31 Jacob S. Hacker & Paul Pierson, Off Center: The Republican Revolution and the Erosion of American Democracy 187 (2005).

Making matters worse is the replacement  of  the party organization  with  television  politics  and  thus  the  new importance of campaign  finance  to pay for advertising. 32 See John H. Aldrich, Why Parties? The Origin and Transformation of Political Parties in America 270 (1995); see also Anthony J. Gaughan, The Forty-Year War on Money in Politics: Watergate, FECA, and the Future of Campaign Finance Reform, 77 Ohio St. L.J. 791, 811–13 (2016). Of course,  money  has  always  been  important in politics,  but television ads were particularly expensive,  as were the associ­ated media consulting and production costs. 33 See Gaughan, supra note 32, at 811–13. The political parties of the 1960s, near the start of the television age, were equipped for a different style of retail politics, not the fundraising- and media-focused campaign­ing then coming into importance. 34 See Aldrich, supra note 32, at 269–73. Candidates therefore needed to raise money elsewhere for their advertising  campaigns  and  reached  out directly  to  private donors to fund them. 35 See Gaughan, supra note 32, at 812 (explaining that “[c]andidates have been on a fundraising treadmill” since the emergence of modern, advertising-based political campaigns). Party politics thus shifted dramati­cally in focus and operation from  the  1960s  to  the  1990s. 36 See Abu El-Haj, supra note 1, at 1257 (“The national committees of the two major political parties, for example, largely function as vessels through which to collect and distribute donations.”). Donors became the candidates’ primary audience, in Professor Abu El-Haj’s opinion, far ahead of regular citizens. 37 See id. at 1264–65. And again,  the empirical literature thoroughly substantiates the suspicion that politicians hew more closely to the preferences of campaign donors and party activists than regular voters. 38 See, e.g., Stephanopoulos, supra note 10, at 1577–79, 1595 (finding, in accord with prior studies, “that the poor are relatively powerless at both the federal and state levels,” meaning that policymakers are responsive only to the wealthy).

The parties have therefore been hollowed out as political associa­tions. Professor Abu El-Haj laments the decline of participatory politics that has followed from this shift. She explains that the “urban machine politics that depended on the confluence of relatively strong personal ties and a formal organization bound by patronage is long gone.” 39 Abu El-Haj, supra note 1, at 1256. This hollowing out of the major parties, for Professor Abu El-Haj, is critical to understanding their modern dysfunctions. The disconnection of the major parties from ordinary folks, the so-called party faithful, has meant that the parties lost touch with everyday America. 40 See id. at 1267–68. The parties are respon­sive mainly to the politician and donor classes who largely come from the socioeconomic elite rather than “individuals with more typical experience of American life—individuals who have never had a white-collar professional job, women who have left their young, school-age chil­dren at home with siblings because they cannot afford daycare, or those who regularly navigate the criminal justice or welfare systems.” 41 Id. at 1266.

Professor Abu El-Haj’s special contribution here is linking our hol­lowed-out parties to the overarching problem of democratic nonre­sponsive­ness. Although others have cited the same literature on the parties’ detachment from the concerns of regular citizens, Professor Abu El-Haj connects this depressing trend to the diminishment of mass participation in the major parties. 42 See id. at 1265–67. As she reasons it, “[T]he heyday of membership-based routes to political power was also the New Deal period during which federal policy was significantly more attentive to the needs of middle-class Americans.” 43 Id. at 1270–71. Bolstering democratic accountability therefore “lies in strengthening elected officials’ social ties to activists and activists’ ties to a broad and representative electorate, through the use of peer-to-peer strategies.” 44 Id. at 1232. Professor Abu El-Haj cites the extensive empirical literature on social networks and political participation to argue that “[r]elationships and social networks, far more than ideology and belief, drive political recruitment and sustain political activism.” 45 Id. at 1259 & n.162. Along these lines, she champions the rebuilding of the major parties as political associations that would once again embody these values and social ties. At the center of this party-associational path, Professor Abu El-Haj advocates “cultivating, strengthening, and broadening social ties within partisan networks [as] an alternative, and underappreciated, path to responsive and accountable governance.” 46 Id. at 1250.

What’s distinctive about Professor Abu El-Haj’s perspective is that she, unlike other election law scholars, does not look to the party leader­ship or greater electoral competition as an answer. Viewing the same parti­san dysfunction, Professor Richard Pildes calls for further deregula­tion of campaign finance to empower party leaders and other elites with greater leverage over the party coalition to steer it back to center. 47 See Pildes, supra note 24, at 836–45 (describing recommendations for empower­ing political parties through campaign finance deregulation). Pildes, in this vein, believes that partisan competition would induce party leaders toward ideological moderation if only they had more control over party activists and outside groups such as Super PACs. 48 See id. at 828–33 (“Party-based contributions to campaigns are a force for modera­tion compared to individual contributions.”). But Professor Abu El-Haj argues that the larger problem is that wealthy donors with extreme ideological preferences already have outsized influence over party politics and might simply dominate party leaders even further if campaign finance deregulation made those leaders yet more reliant on their money. 49 See Abu El-Haj, supra note 1, at 1282–83. Instead, as she puts it, “curtailing the political influence of donors and other unrepresentative policy demanders requires creating a counterpoint to that influence by empowering and mobilizing millions of ordinary Americans through civic and political organizations.” 50 Id. at 1284.

Unlike Pildes, Professor Abu El-Haj does not assume party leaders have natural incentives toward moderation and partisan competitiveness. Reforming the parties, then, requires more than simply empowering party leaders. As a consequence, courts and scholars have wrongly placed all their eggs in the basket of responsible party government, which is a “colossal mistake” that “has not panned out.” 51 Id. at 1230. Even as the parties became more competitive with each other in many respects over the last fifty years, Professor Abu El-Haj argues that they actually became less respon­sive to regular Americans and even their party faithful because the changing internal dynamics of the parties shifted too much influence into the hands of the politicians and donor class. 52 See supra note 5 and accompanying text.

For this reason, Professor Abu El-Haj advocates an “associational-party perspective” that accepts parties “for what they are—associations dominated by self-interested political elites”—but also seeks to open par­ties to “the political participation of ordinary citizens as agents rather than consumers.” 53 Abu El-Haj, supra note 1, at 1233. Rather than conceiving of parties mainly as ideologi­cal speakers with a passive audience of voters, Professor Abu El-Haj argues for exploring “the part associations can play in mobilizing and informing citizens and in facilitating a two-way street of communication between party leaders and ordinary voters.” 54 Id. at 1232. It is necessary to change the inputs and influences on party leadership, which in turn changes the party leadership, to reform the parties. The theory of responsible party government, in her view, wrongheadedly trusted party leaders and party competition to produce responsiveness, while an associational-party perspec­tive makes no such assumption. Professor Abu El-Haj would reform the party from within by democratizing its internal composition. 55 See id. at 1254–55 (“While responsible party government adopted a relatively formalist conception of the party as its officers, the associational-party path exploits the sociological fact that the contemporary party organization is a network of individuals and groups connected formally and informally in their efforts to influence elections and govern­ment policy.”).

B. Constitutional Law and the Associational Party

What does this have to do with constitutional law? Professor Abu El-Haj correctly points out that a theory of responsible party government “underpins the Court’s jurisprudence on the First Amendment rights of political parties.” 56 Id. at 1229. Most notably, in disputes between the party member­ship and leadership over party affairs, the Court has sided with the leader­ship as the guardian of a political party’s ideological and political brand. 57 See, e.g., Michael S. Kang, The Hydraulics and Politics of Party Regulation, 91 Iowa L. Rev. 131, 139 (2005) (“[T]he Court has been excessively solicitous of the leaders of the major parties and thus suppressed political vitality in American politics by striking down regulations that would have helped to democratize the process.”); Nathaniel Persily, Toward a Functional Defense of Political Party Autonomy, 76 N.Y.U. L. Rev. 750, 752 (2001) (“The Court has been quite aggressive in protecting parties’ rights to define their primary electorate . . . .”). This guardianship encompasses control over nomination pro­cesses and party organization against challenges from rank-and-file mem­bers, candidates, and government regulation. These decisions assume, sometimes explicitly, that the leadership will position the party to com­pete electorally and can therefore be trusted to strategically balance the party’s ideological interests against the electorate’s preferences. 58 See Abu El-Haj, supra note 1, at 1252. But Professor Abu El-Haj argues that this judicial bet on the party leadership has proved to be “fool’s gold” that fails to produce accountability. 59 Id.

Instead of doubling down on party competition and responsible party government, Professor Abu El-Haj proposes that courts alter First Amendment doctrine to “enhance opportunities for social contact between party elites and the broader electorate.” 60 Id. at 1286. In cases involving regula­tion of parties, she would deemphasize the party leadership’s control of the party brand by having courts weigh any effect on the par­ties’ “capacity to foster deep and wide social ties to a representative elec­torate.” 61 Id. at 1288. She would have courts complicate the traditional First Amendment analysis of the party as speaker juxtaposed against the state as regulator by instead incorporating an assessment of how regulation affects the capacity of regular voters to engage the parties.

Specifically, Professor Abu El-Haj suggests an extension of Anderson–Burdick balancing—used by courts to weigh regulation mainly of election administration—to “all manner of political party regulations,” including campaign finance law. 62 Id. at 1286. Under the Anderson–Burdick test, courts weigh the injury to voters’ First and Fourteenth Amendment rights against “‘the precise interests put forward by the State as justifications for the burden imposed by its rule,’ taking into consideration ‘the extent to which those interests make it necessary to burden the plaintiff’s rights.’” Burdick v. Takushi, 504 U.S. 428, 434 (1992) (quoting Tashjian v. Republican Party of Conn., 479 U.S. 208, 214 (1986)). To illustrate her proposal, she applies it to the Court’s decision in McConnell v. FEC 63 540 U.S. 93 (2003), overruled in part by Citizens United v. FEC, 558 U.S. 310 (2010). to uphold the provision of the Bipartisan Campaign Reform Act (BCRA) that banned party “soft money.” 64 See Abu El-Haj, supra note 1, at 1293–96; see also McConnell, 540 U.S. at 122–26, 146–47 (upholding BCRA’s restrictions on soft money). “Soft money is collected outside the usual strictures of the federal campaign regulation[s] . . . [governing] express advocacy. The FEC originally authorized the collection of soft money for use mainly on ‘party build­ing’ activity, including voter registration, get-out-the-vote activities, and general administra­tion, rather than for federal electioneering.” Michael S. Kang, The Brave New World of Party Campaign Finance Law, 101 Cornell L. Rev. 531, 586 (2016) [hereinafter Kang, Brave New World] (footnote omitted). However, the major party committees soon exploited this interpretation and used soft money to fund “sham issue advertising” that closely resembled “hard money” electioneer­ing. See Kang, Brave New World, supra, at 586–87. The amount of soft money skyrocketed during the 1990s to the point that it approached half of national party fundraising before it was banned in 2002. 65 See Michael J. Malbin, Political Parties Under the Post-McConnell Bipartisan Campaign Reform Act, 3 Election L.J. 177, 177 (2004) (“The six major party national commit­tees raised almost $500 million in soft money in 2001–2002. This was more than 40% of their total receipts.”); see also Bipartisan Campaign Reform Act of 2002, Pub. L. No. 107-155, § 101, 116 Stat. 81, 82–86 (codified as amended at 52 U.S.C. § 30125 (Supp. IV 2017)) (enacting a ban on political parties raising soft money). Unrestricted soft money to the national party commit­tees, some­times in million-dollar denominations, raised major concerns about cam­paign finance corruption and undue influence over party actors. The Court in McConnell upheld the federal soft-money ban on these grounds. 66 See McConnell, 540 U.S. at 143. But soft money also funded, because of legal require­ments about how it was spent, grassroots party activities at the state and local levels. When BCRA banned soft money, funding for these activities dried up. 67 See Kate Andrias, Hollowed-Out Democracy, 89 N.Y.U. L. Rev. Online 48, 48–50 (2014), http://www.nyulawreview.org/sites/default/files/pdf/nyulawreviewonline-89-48-andrias_0.pdf [https://perma.cc/ATX9-GWCS] (criticizing the “hollowed-out” parties and noting the larger absence of participatory institutions); Joseph Fishkin & Heather K. Gerken, The Party’s Over: McCutcheon, Shadow Parties, and the Future of the Party System, 2014 Sup. Ct. Rev. 175, 204 (lamenting the deterioration of the parties’ role in democratic mobilization and engagement); Samuel Issacharoff, Market Intermediaries in the Post-Buckley World, 89 N.Y.U. L. Rev. Online 105, 109–10 (2014), http://www.nyulawreview.org/sites/default/files/pdf/nyulawreviewonline-89-105-issacharoff.pdf [https://perma.cc/LE29-9YGJ] (arguing that state-level party infrastructure no longer exists and must be “created on the fly” for national campaigns).

Sensitive to this type of effect on parties as associations, Professor Abu El-Haj believes that Anderson–Burdick balancing would focus on two new critical questions: (1) “whether the regulation decreases a party’s ability to mobilize political participation and facilitate information transmis­sion through peer-to-peer appeals by party activists;” and (2) “whether it otherwise undermines the party’s organizational stability and coalition-building capacity.” 68 Abu El-Haj, supra note 1, at 1293. She illustrates how First Amendment law omits consideration of these questions, instead focusing on the usual corrup­tion and expressive-interest analysis. 69 See id. at 1291–93, 1298–99. Although Professor Abu El-Haj cagily stops short of arguing McConnell should have struck down the soft-money ban, she demonstrates that Anderson–Burdick balancing, as she conceives it, leads to a constitutional analysis that “is significantly differ­ent from the current state of the party jurisprudence.” 70 Id. at 1298–99.

II. What Can and Should Courts Do?

Professor Abu El-Haj’s rich diagnosis of the problems with today’s par­ties—that is, capture by wealthy donors and ideological extremists, disconnection from regular voters, and organizational hollowing out—is almost undeniable, but I am less sure about her proposals to fix them. To be fair, today’s major parties present deep-rooted problems that are diffi­cult to fix. But that’s partially the point—many of the changes to the par­ties over the past fifty years have a broad historical arc that transcends the Court’s First Amendment case law and therefore are not easy to alter through a new judicial approach.

First, the diagnosis. Professor Abu El-Haj is clearly correct that today’s major parties are very different from the political associations they were fifty years ago. Parties have always served as vehicles for politi­cians to coordinate with like-minded voters and activists. For most of American history, parties were mass-membership organizations of one sort or another that sprang into action during elections to mobilize volun­teers and voters. 71 See Aldrich, supra note 32, at 97–98. Along with newspapers and other print media, party organizations communicated information to voters and bonded regular citizens to the party ticket through the face-to-face relationships that Professor Abu El-Haj celebrates. She is dead-on about the disappear­ance of these thick networks of party relationships between regular folks and party officials and politicians. As she puts it aptly, “For the average voter, computer-generated requests for donations have replaced the ward boss as the personal face of the party.” 72 Abu El-Haj, supra note 1, at 1265.

But why has this happened? I do not think that the Court’s jurispru­dence on election administration or campaign finance is the main rea­son. As I hinted above, the partisan realignment of the past fifty years occurred coextensively with the rise of television politics. Television, and more specifically television advertising, intruded into American house­holds and replaced party networks and retail politics as the principal means by which candidates could reach voters. 73 See Aldrich, supra note 32, at 270. Candidates once needed to climb the local party hierarchy and eventually win the party bosses’ nod before relying on the party machine to mobilize loyal party voters on election day. The party machine doled out favors and jobs to the reliant faithful, who ensured that the party ranks turned out en masse at the polls to elect whomever the party bosses had placed on the ticket as their nominees. 74 See id. at 269 (“The party held an effective monopoly on the resources . . . that were necessary to run an effective campaign for local, state, or national office. Ambitious politicians therefore could realize their long-term career [and short-term electoral] ambi­tions . . . only through the agency of the party.”).

However, the parties eventually adopted primary elections to decide their nominations in place of party bosses. Television then enabled candi­dates to reach voters directly and establish a personal brand independent of the party label. 75 See id. at 269–74 (describing the influence of television on political parties and their structure). Television and other forms of mass media allowed party candidates and party voters to coordinate on election day without the mediating authority of party bosses and machine politics. 76 See id. at 270. What’s more, prohibitions on party patronage shrank the influence of party bosses even further, stripping them of their control over the party organiza­tion and volunteers that candidates once relied on. 77 See id. When com­bined with the contemporaneous realignment of the parties into uni­form ideological coalitions, American politics today is less about face-to-face, bread-and-butter relationships and more about ideological commitments that can be afforded, in terms of time and money, largely by a richer, more privileged class.

Professor Abu El-Haj is probably right that the decline of the party organ­ization has meant disconnection from the regular rank-and-file who once constituted the major parties. Professor Abu El-Haj reports duti­fully that today’s political activists tend to be whiter, wealthier, and more educated than the rest of the electorate. 78 See Abu El-Haj, supra note 1, at 1271. What’s less clear is how and whether one can return to the days of yore that she implicitly extols. The dynamics I have described are overarching trends in American soci­ety and politics that are unlikely to be reversed very easily. Professor Abu El-Haj admits that “[a]ffirmative strategies to compensate for our social landscape would need to be devised” to overcome the ways that modern politics have evolved away from the participatory politics of a half century ago. 79 Id. at 1272. This requirement is challenging because, as Professor Abu El-Haj again agrees, “party activists may have very little interest in facilitating responsiveness to the electorate” and “are likely to be wary of broad mobiliza­tion.” 80 Id. at 1274. Despite these changes, Professor Abu El-Haj insists that parties “have yet to shed their essential associational attributes” and “remain networks of individuals and groups—activists, donors, officehold­ers, and dealmakers—tied together and to the electorate by social connections of various strengths.” 81 Id. at 1256–57. She argues that we live in a spe­cial moment following the 2016 election when elites should be aware of the costs of ignoring the dissatisfaction and disaffection of regular peo­ple, from whom they’ve insulated themselves. 82 See id. at 1275.

That said, these are still deep structural changes to American society and politics that have contributed to the participatory decline and that are unlikely to be undone. 83 Of course, an overarching decline of American civic participation has occurred over the past half century that includes but transcends the major parties. See generally Robert D. Putnam, Bowling Alone: The Collapse and Revival of American Community (2000); Theda Skocpol, Diminished Democracy: From Membership to Management in American Civic Life (2003). Patronage, for one, was a foundation of the rich political associations we used to call the party machine. 84 See generally Robert Yablon, Campaigns, Inc., 103 Minn. L. Rev. 151 (2018) (offering a nice overview). Patronage offered solidary benefits to regular neighborhood folks in the form of jobs, favors, and material rewards as a payoff for party loyalty and votes. 85 See Fiorina, supra note 29, at 530–31 (arguing that traditional parties fifty years ago offered material rewards through patronage and other means in place of today’s cur­rency of ideological payoffs). The party machine and its loyal following cared little about highfaluting ideological principles compared with neighborhood camaraderie and spreading the spoils of government riches across the community. 86 See id. at 532–35. Professor Abu El-Haj implicitly celebrates the participatory culture fed by the machine, but it is hard to imagine its restoration in the modern era. The rejection of machine politics and party patronage has constitutional pedigree; the Court has held that government employment conditioned on partisan affiliation or allegiance was unconstitutional under the First Amendment, subject only to narrow exceptions. 87 See, e.g., Rutan v. Republican Party of Ill., 497 U.S. 62, 65 (1990) (holding that promotion, transfer, recall, and hiring decisions involving low-level public employees may not be based on party affiliation and support); Elrod v. Burns, 427 U.S. 347, 373 (1976) (“We hold . . . that the practice of patronage dismissals is unconstitutional under the First and Fourteenth Amendments . . . .”). Just as importantly, American political culture has shifted so decisively against patronage that civil service bans on patronage are standard practice at almost every level of government. 88 See, e.g., Megan Glasheen, Patronage Employment Practices and the First Amendment, 34 How. L.J. 663, 667–68 (1991) (“All of the states have enacted some form of civil service legislation [banning patronage].”).

The decline of union membership and political power has also trans­formed political participation, at least within the Democratic Party. Once a pillar of the Democratic Party’s workforce, union members provided a committed volunteer base and constituency that saw its economic fate tied up with the Party. 89 See Jake Rosenfeld, What Unions No Longer Do 159–61 (2014). Not only did union members partici­pate in party affairs at higher rates than other citizens; 90 See, e.g., Jasmine Kerrissey & Evan Schofer, Union Membership and Political Participation in the United States, 91 Soc. Forces 895, 930 (2013) (“[W]e observe large and significant effects of [union] membership on volunteering and political donations.”). unions them­selves also mobi­lized nonunion members on behalf of the Democrats and boosted overall political participation. 91 See Benjamin I. Sachs, The Unbundled Union: Politics Without Collective Bargaining, 123 Yale L.J. 148, 168–76 (2013); Roland Zullo, Union Membership and Political Inclusion, 62 Indus. & Lab. Rel. Rev. 22, 32 (2008). However, union member­ship has declined dramat­ically over the past fifty years. 92 See Rosenfeld, supra note 89, at 1–9 (documenting the decline of American unions over the past half century). This decline in union member­ship, and therefore union resources and political efficacy, has contri­buted to a decline in political participation over the same period. 93 See Jan E. Leighley & Jonathan Nagler, Unions, Voter Turnout, and Class Bias in the U.S. Electorate, 1964–2004, 69 J. Pol. 430, 439 (2007) (“[T]urnout would have been approximately 3 percentage points higher in 2004 had unions remained as strong as they were in 1964.”). What is more, the Court has eroded union activism by limiting unions’ ability to collect fees to fund their activities, 94 See generally Benjamin I. Sachs, Agency Fees and the First Amendment, 131 Harv. L. Rev. 1046, 1052–55 (2018) (detailing the major Supreme Court cases concerning agency fees). most recently last Term in Janus v. American Federation of State, County, & Municipal Employees, Council 31. 95 See 138 S. Ct. 2448, 2459–60 (2018) (holding that agency fees imposed by public-sector unions are unconstitutional).

Another objection is that courts are quite unlikely to adopt the associa­tional-party perspective that Professor Abu El-Haj urges. Of course, this appeal to feasibility is often fatuous because academics both test the limits of possibility and press their normative values. 96 See Kang, Brave New World, supra note 64, at 577–79 (arguing that academics and reformers should map reform strategies over the long term and not be deterred by short-term political infeasibility, which changes as immediately as judicial personnel changes). But  it  is  worth  noting that Professor Abu El-Haj turns away from competition-ori­ented approaches  to  political  parties  partially  because  the  Court  “has  been  singularly unreceptive  to  adopting  a  procompetition  theory  of  the  First Amendment.” 97 Abu El-Haj, supra note 1, at 1231. Along the same lines, though, the Court has rejected Justice Stevens’s dissenting view,  which mirrors much of Professor Abu El-Haj’s approach,  in  some  of  the party cases she dis­cusses. 98 See, e.g., Cal. Democratic Party v. Jones, 530 U.S. 567, 584–85 (2000) (rejecting the promotion of fairness, increased voter choice, and increased voter participation as sufficient state interests to uphold California’s blanket primary); Timmons v. Twin Cities Area New Party, 520 U.S. 351, 369–70 (1997) (rejecting Justice Stevens’s argument in dis­sent while upholding Minnesota’s antifusion laws prohibiting candidates from appearing on the ballot as a candidate of multiple political parties); Burdick v. Takushi, 504 U.S. 428, 430, 442–44 (1992) (upholding a state ban on write-in votes, over a dissenting opinion joined by Justice Stevens, which argued that voters “dissatisfied with the choices available to them” were impermissibly burdened). Most prominently,  in California Democratic Party v. Jones,  Justice Stevens argued  in  dissent  that  California’s blanket primary should have been upheld,  notwithstanding the state-facilitated intrusion of nonmem­bers into the parties’ nomination processes. 99 Jones, 530 U.S. at 590–92 (Stevens, J., dissenting). Justice Stevens argued that “[w]hen a State acts  not  to  limit democratic participation but to expand the ability of individuals to participate in the democratic process,  it is act­ing not as a foe of the First Amendment  but  as  a  friend and ally.” 100 Id. at 595–96. Justice Stevens would have upheld the blanket primary because he found compel­ling the state’s interest in “[i]ncreasing the representativeness of elected officials, giving voters greater choice,  and increasing voter turn­out and participation.” 101 Id. at 600 (alteration in original) (internal quotation marks omitted) (quoting Cal. Democratic Party v. Jones, 169 F.3d 646, 662 (9th Cir. 1999), rev’d, 530 U.S. 567 (2000)). This view, similar to Professor Abu El-Haj’s, was rejected by the majority and has no greater currency today with the Roberts Court. 102 See, e.g., N.Y. State Bd. of Elections v. Lopez Torres, 552 U.S. 196, 207 (2008) (“[Respondents] argue that the existence of entrenched ‘one-party rule’ demands that the First Amendment be used to impose additional competition in the nominee-selection pro­cess of the parties. . . . This is a novel and implausible reading of the First Amendment.”).

In any event, political participation and the democratization of the par­ties may be an area in which courts simply can do little affirmatively to help at this point. Legislatures author the primary regulatory choices that structure society and politics, while courts largely react to restrict them through judicial review when they see fit. But courts lack the broader affirma­tive authority it would take to revitalize American democratic life through a “party-reform agenda tailored to strengthening the associational life of political parties” that Professor Abu El-Haj proposes. 103 Abu El-Haj, supra note 1, at 1283. Courts strike down unconstitutional choices and trim legislative overexten­sion, but they can do little more to encourage adoption of wise legislative choices other than stand aside when they are made. Courts may do best to help merely by avoiding additional harm. This secondary posture is in the nature of the judicial role when it comes to much politi­cal reform. Professor Abu El-Haj may be right about the value and effects of her proposals, but her arguments might be better directed toward legisla­tures than courts.

The same is true for her specific arguments in favor of soft money in campaign finance. I, too, have proposed loosening restrictions on soft-money fundraising for the same reasons that Professor Abu El-Haj cites, but I pitched my appeal to the legislative process, rather than courts. 104 See Kang, Brave New World, supra note 64, at 586–88. It is much more difficult for courts to direct the affirmative project of construc­tive reform themselves. There’s not too much courts can do to encourage adoption of subsidies for grassroots party building other than uphold them when legislatures finally make wise choices to enact them. Courts have a weak institutional hand to play unless legislatures and other policymaking bodies act first.

The larger problem is that the Supreme Court has already done the harm it should have avoided by constitutionalizing so much of campaign finance law. As I just hinted, I share Professor Abu El-Haj’s belief that soft money helps build party capacity and deepen grassroots political involve­ment. There is little doubt that McConnell upholding the BCRA soft-money ban removed funding for state and local parties that benefited from federal soft money. 105 See supra notes 66–67 and accompanying text. But I also think that McConnell was correct in upholding the soft-money ban in deference to Congress’s determination that unfettered soft-money fundraising posed a corruption risk. Courts should hesitate, absent convincing grounds, to strike down campaign finance regulation whether it expands funding for grassroots activities or not. Unfortunately, the Roberts Court instead has aggressively cleared the field of campaign finance regulation over the past decade by striking down contribution limits, 106 See McCutcheon v. FEC, 572 U.S. 185, 227 (2014). source restrictions, 107 See Citizens United v. FEC, 558 U.S. 310, 372 (2010). and fundraising trig­gers 108 See Ariz. Free Enter. Club’s Freedom Club PAC v. Bennett, 564 U.S. 721, 728 (2011). in the name of free speech. Judicial deregulation of campaign finance has thus tied the hands of most kinds of political reform through campaign finance regulation and sent reform proposals in the direction of even further deregulation as the only available option in the area. 109 See, e.g., Raymond J. La Raja & Brian F. Schaffner, Campaign Finance and Political Polarizations: When Purists Prevail 134 (2015) (advocating for a “‘party-centered’ campaign finance system” that would allow “more money [to] flow through parties” and thereby “boost the influence of the pragmatist wing[s] of the part[ies] by making party organizations more salient in elections”); Pildes, supra note 24, at 807, 836–45 (advocating a party-based campaign finance system “aimed at giving the political parties . . . more influ­ence in elections”).

I would hesitate then to instruct courts, per Professor Abu El-Haj’s pro­posal, to look for opportunities to strike down even more legislative regulation of politics in the name of political participation. Her pro­posed balancing would be difficult to apply—so difficult, in fact, that I’m unsure whether Professor Abu El-Haj believes McConnell should have struck down the soft-money ban. Did the costs for grassroots activity funded by soft money outweigh the compelling corruption risks found by Congress to result from soft-money fundraising? Balancing the diffuse interests, typically with little empirical foundation for prospectively judg­ing the former, is sufficiently challenging that it might not be worth the candle. Courts may get their analysis wrong and end up doing more harm than good over the long run.

Indeed, my bet is that formal party leadership is more likely to oppose Professor Abu El-Haj’s desired democratization of their internal affairs than it is to be a willing participant. As Professor Abu El-Haj acknowl­edges, the incumbent party leadership can be expected to favor today’s institutional structures that ensure its continued authority over party affairs. 110 See Abu El-Haj, supra note 1, at 1274. If that’s true, the democratization of the parties is more likely to be achieved by government regulation over the party leader­ship’s opposition. And judicial deference to such regulation is most likely to affirm reform measures that “enhance opportunities for social contact between party elites and the broader electorate.” 111 Id. at 1233. By contrast, the courts’ traditional approach with regard to party regulation has been party autonomy, under which courts have struck down regulation that infringes on party leadership’s discretion over party affairs. 112 See, e.g., N.Y. State Bd. of Elections v. Lopez Torres, 552 U.S. 196 (2008); Cal. Democratic Party v. Jones, 530 U.S. 567 (2000); Tashjian v. Republican Party of Conn., 479 U.S. 208 (1986). It’s pre­cisely this judicial aggressiveness over such regulation to which Professor Abu El-Haj objects. 113 See Abu El-Haj, supra note 1, at 1287. For this reason, we might expect Professor Abu El-Haj actually to want less judicial scrutiny over party regulation and greater deference to government attempts to democratize the parties over counter­vailing objections by the party leadership.

In other words, Professor Abu El-Haj may be absolutely right in her diag­nosis of the parties’ democratic deficit and even her prescriptions about how to cure them, but courts may be the wrong institution to spear­head this type of reform.

Conclusion

Professor Abu El-Haj is undeniably persuasive in her diagnosis of mod­ern party politics and her central claim that responsible party govern­ment has not resulted from today’s First Amendment approach to political parties. It is less clear if courts can really do much to reverse the pathologies she identifies so insightfully. Directing her suggestions toward legislative regulation and party reform could be more productive than focusing on courts. 114 See, e.g., David Weigel, Democrats Weaken ‘Superdelegates’ in Effort to Avoid Another Bitter Presidential Primary, Wash. Post (Aug. 25, 2018), https://www.washingtonpost.com/politics/democrats-weaken-superdelegates-in-effort-to-avoid-another-bitter-presidential-primary/2018/08/25/f45c6512-a7be-11e8-a656-943eefab5daf_story.html [https://perma.cc/8C7G-VBEJ] (describing a successful effort to change internal Democratic Party rules that had previously empowered “superdelegates,” party insiders and elected officials “whose presidential convention votes were not bound to the results of primaries or caucuses”). Perhaps, though, the larger payoff is that trust­ing courts to affirmatively inject a greater interest in participatory politics is a second-best strategy that has its limitations but is still better than the courts’ current approach. Given the dysfunctional state of today’s party politics, maybe that’s justification enough.