PANHANDLING REGULATION AFTER REED V. TOWN OF GILBERT

PANHANDLING REGULATION AFTER REED V. TOWN OF GILBERT

In Reed v. Town of Gilbert the Supreme Court rearticulated the standard for when regulation of speech is content based. This determination has already had a large impact on cases involving panhandling regulations and is likely to result in the invalidation of the majority of this nation’s panhandling laws.

This Note will begin with a discussion of First Amendment doctrine and how panhandling is protected speech. This Note will then demonstrate that it is helpful to think of panhandling regulations categorically and explore how these categories of panhandling laws have fared in lower courts. This Note will then discuss the holding in Reed and how jurisdictions have already begun to invalidate panhandling laws.  Finally, this Note proposes using the captive audience doctrine to uphold the validity of some salutary panhandling regulations while in­val­idating laws that are burdensome and oppressive to free expression.

Introduction

In the summer of 2015, the nation’s attention once again focused intently on the highest court of the land as the Supreme Court delivered dramatic decisions on issues including gay marriage, 1 Obergefell v. Hodges, 135 S. Ct. 2584 (2015). Obamacare, 2 King v. Burwell, 135 S. Ct. 2480 (2015). and housing discrimination. 3 Tex. Dep’t of Hous. & Cmty. Affairs v. Inclusive Cmtys. Project, Inc., 135 S. Ct. 2507 (2015).

It is a small wonder, then, that a decision concerning signage regulation in the Phoenix suburb of Gilbert received scant attention 4 Reed v. Town of Gilbert, 135 S. Ct. 2218 (2015); see also Adam Liptak, Court’s Free-Speech Expansion Has Far-Reaching Consequences, N.Y. Times (Aug. 17, 2015), http://www.nytimes.com/2015/08/18/us/politics/courts-free-speech-expansion-has-far-reaching-consequences.html (on file with the Columbia Law Review) [hereinafter Liptak, Court’s Free-Speech Expansion] (calling Reed a “sleeper case” of 2015 term). and a decision remanding a case about panhandling in Worcester, Massachusetts received next to none. 5 Thayer v. City of Worcester, 135 S. Ct. 2887 (2015) (mem.); cf. David G. Savage, Death Penalty, Same-Sex Marriage and Air Pollution: Supreme Court’s Most Important Decisions This Term, L.A. Times (June 29, 2015, 7:36 am), http://www.latimes .com/nation/la-na-court-key-cases-2015-20150526-story.html [http://perma.cc/8GJM-E6Y8] (failing to include Thayer or Gilbert on list of thirteen important decisions from 2015 Supreme Court term). While ordinary Americans (and indeed perhaps some of those in legal academia) may have never heard of Reed v. Town of Gilbert or Thayer v. City of Worcester, these two cases signify a coming sea change in how American municipalities regulate their streets and police their most vulnerable and indigent populations.

In Reed, Justice Thomas articulated a new standard for courts to assess the content neutrality of laws regulating speech, 6 Reed, 135 S. Ct. at 2228–29 (stating first step in analysis is “determining whether the law is content neutral on its face”). a move likely to have profound consequences on a broad array of subjects from advertising regulations to securities laws because deciding a law is content based is virtually tantamount to deciding it is unconstitutional. 7 See infra section I.A.2 (discussing importance of content neutrality); see also Liptak, Court’s Free-Speech Expansion, supra note 4 (quoting Yale Law School Dean Robert Post stating Reed will have far-reaching consequences). This Note focuses on the often-ignored area of panhandling where Reed has already had tremendous effect: In Thayer, the Supreme Court remanded a decision by former-Justice Souter to be decided in accordance with Reed. 8 Thayer, 135 S. Ct. at 2887. This decision signals that the Supreme Court views Reed as the new standard for content-neutrality determinations and that it fully expects this standard to alter panhandling jurisprudence.

The Court’s dismantling of the constitutionality of panhandling regulations will affect cities across America that have passed laws regulating and curbing panhandling, particularly focusing on the problem of beggars that aggressively solicit donations. 9 See Dan Frosch, Homeless Are Fighting Back Against Panhandling Bans, N.Y. Times (Oct. 5, 2012), http://www.nytimes.com/2012/10/06/us/homeless-are-fighting-back-in-court-against-panhandling-bans.html (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (“[C]ities across the country have been cracking down on an apparent rise in aggressive panhandling . . . .”); see also Richard Fausset, With This Many Buskers in Asheville, a Discordant Note Was Inevitable, N.Y. Times (May 16, 2015), http://www.nytimes.com/ 2015/05/17/us/with-this-many-buskers-in-asheville-a-discordant-note-was-inevitable.html (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (discussing consideration of new ordinances regulating street performers soliciting donations in Asheville). Albuquerque outlaws all panhandling that occurs within three feet of a potential donor, unless the donor has agreed to donate. 10 Albuquerque Code of Ordinances § 12-2-28 (2014). Fort Lauderdale prohibits soliciting for alms on its beaches. 11 See Smith v. City of Fort Lauderdale, 177 F.3d 954, 955 (11th Cir. 1999). And the City of San Antonio has even considered penalizing those who give to beggars. 12 See Myra Arthur, SAPD Chief Abandons Panhandling Proposal, KSAT 12 (Oct. 1, 2014 9:21 pm), http://www.ksat.com/content/pns/ksat/news/2014/10/01/sapd-chief-abandons-panhandling-proposal.html [http://perma.cc/C9RE-YGC6] (noting proposal supported by San Antonio Police Chief to criminalize giving money to panhandlers failed due to lack of support from city council). New York City bans soliciting donations on its subways, 13 See N.Y. Comp. Codes R. & Regs. tit. 21, § 1050.6(b)(2) (2015) (outlawing “solicitation of money” in New York subway system). The Port Authority of New York and New Jersey also bans panhandling at the World Trade Center site and the Port Authority Bus Terminal. See id. §§ 1220.16, 1290.3(d). as well as aggressive begging, 14 N.Y.C. Administrative Code § 10-136 (LEXIS through March 2015).     and is currently looking for a method to curb costumed characters and topless women from asking for donations in Times Square. 15 See Josh Dawsey & Adam Janos, De Blasio Takes Aim at Panhandling by Topless Women in Times Square, Wall St. J. (Aug. 18, 2015, 11:37 pm), http://www.wsj. com/articles/de-blasio-takes-aim-at-panhandling-by-topless-women-in-times-square-14399 45701 (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (discussing attempts by city to regulate panhandling in Times Square); Thomas MacMillan, Curb the Times Square Tip-Seekers, Lawmakers Say, Wall St. J. (Mar. 28, 2016, 7:24 pm), http://www.wsj.com/articles/curb-the-times-square-tip-seekers-lawmakers-say-1459207369 (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (same). As this Note discusses, these panhandling regulations differ greatly from one another, with some laws outlawing all conduct and others more carefully targeting harmful behavior. 16 See infra Part III (discussing need to view panhandling regulations as categories). This Note will also argue that appellate courts have been treating different categories of panhandling regulation differently. See infra section II.B.2 (discussing pattern of appellate rules on different categories of panhandling law). With the recent decision in Reed, however, there is a real danger that virtually all panhandling laws will be invalidated, even though some serve to protect pedestrians and others.

As anyone who has lived in an urban environment knows, panhandling takes many forms, ranging from musicians playing concertos with their violin cases on the sidewalk to encourage donations to an imposing homeless man demanding money in a secluded alley. 17 For example, New York City’s anti-aggressive begging law groups together soliciting, asking, and begging, which it defines as: “[U]sing the spoken, written, or printed word, or bodily gestures, signs or other means with the purpose of obtaining an immediate donation of money or other thing of value or soliciting the sale of goods or services.” N.Y.C. Administrative Code § 10-136. Instead, this Note defines panhandling as any in-person solicitation for immediate charitable giving of either cash or goods for the purpose of benefiting the person doing the solicitation. 18 This definition would include the officious intermeddler, such as the infamous “squeegee man,” who provides an unwanted service and then begins soliciting for his or her “compensation.” See Richard A. Epstein, Principles of a Free Society 115 (1998) (defining and discussing “officious intermeddler”). For another definition of panhan­dling, see Norton v. City of Springfield, 768 F.3d 713, 714 (7th Cir. 2014) (“The ordinance defines panhandling as an oral request for an immediate donation of money.”), rev’d, 806 F.3d 411 (7th Cir. 2015). This definition therefore excludes face-to-face solicitation for third parties or charities. Using this definition, this Note will show that the constitutionality of current panhandling laws is dubious after Reed.

Part I of this Note will discuss background First Amendment doctrine necessary to understand the importance of Reed’s effect on panhandling laws and introduce the captive audience doctrine. Part II will argue that panhandling is protected speech, discuss panhandling laws, and offer a tripartite categorization of those laws. Part II will then discuss how appellate courts before Reed tackled different types of panhandling laws and explain the Reed decision in greater depth. Finally, Part III will show that virtually no panhandling regulations can withstand constitutional scrutiny under Reed and Thayer. It will then offer the solution of balancing the rights of those panhandling with the rights of captive audiences so that courts may retain salubrious panhandling regulations.

I. An Overview of First Amendment Doctrine

This Part explores the current understandings of the First Amendment’s protection of aggressive panhandling and the captive audience doctrine. Section I.A summarizes background on First Amendment doctrine and discusses how courts analyze whether regulations of speech or expression violate the Constitution. Section I.B then explains the captive audience doctrine, which this Note later argues is a possible solution to prevent the wholesale invalidation of panhandling regulations. 19 See infra section III.B (discussing use of captive audience doctrine to analyze aggressive panhandling laws).

A. First Amendment Doctrine

The doctrine surrounding the First Amendment is notoriously complex. 20 See, e.g., Robert Post, Reconciling Theory and Doctrine in First Amendment Jurisprudence, 88 Calif. L. Rev. 2353, 2355 (2000) (“The free speech jurisprudence of the First Amendment is notorious for its flagrantly proliferating and contradictory rules, its profoundly chaotic collection of methods and theories.”). This section summarizes the relevant legal frameworks that courts use to determine whether speech is protected by the First Amendment and if so, how to regulate the protected speech.

1. What Speech Is Protected? — The First Amendment’s mandate that “Congress shall make no law . . . abridging the freedom of speech” 21 U.S. Const. amend. I. is arguably the most famous and sacrosanct in all of American law. 22 See e.g., Whitney v. California, 274 U.S. 357, 375–77 (1927) (Brandeis, J., concurring) (“[The Founders] believed that freedom to think as you will and to speak as you think are means indispensable to the discovery and spread of political truth[;] . . . that public discussion is a political duty; and that this should be a fundamental principle of the American government.”). Despite this ostensibly simple language, determining what “abridgment of the freedom of speech” means is no simple task. Fighting words, obscenity, and threats, for example, fall outside of many of the Constitution’s protections, 23 Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire, 315 U.S. 568, 571–72 (1942) (“[T]he lewd and obscene, the profane, the libelous, and the insulting or ‘fighting’ words[,] . . . epithets or personal abuse [are] not in any proper sense communication of information or opinion safeguarded by the Constitution . . . .”). and governments can often regulate such “low value” speech as long as the law does not discriminate on the basis of viewpoint. 24 See R.A.V. v. City of St. Paul, 505 U.S. 377, 383 (1992) (holding regulations cannot discriminate on viewpoint of speech for categories of speech excluded from First Amendment protection). While this Note mostly discusses whether a law discriminates based on just content, see infra notes 33–36 and accompanying text (discussing content-based discrimination), a law that discriminates based on viewpoint not only discriminates based on content but also chooses a side concerning the regulated speech. To borrow an example from then-Professor Elena Kagan, a law that was only content based would outlaw using a billboard for political candidates while a viewpoint-discriminatory law would outlaw using a billboard for Democrats. Elena Kagan, Private Speech, Public Purpose: The Role of Governmental Motive in First Amendment Doctrine, 63 U. Chi. L. Rev. 413, 444–45 (1996).

Even if an utterance is not unprotected low-value speech, the full aegis of the First Amendment may not protect it. If the speech is commercial in nature, courts apply a less exacting test in determining the validity of the regulation. 25 See Cent. Hudson Gas & Elec. Corp. v. Pub. Serv. Comm’n, 447 U.S. 557, 565–66 (1980) (articulating four-part analysis for determining if commercial speech laws violate First Amendment); see also Bd. of Trs. of State Univ. of N.Y. v. Fox, 492 U.S. 469, 479–80 (1989) (modifying Central Hudson test). The current test for commercial speech considers whether the speech concerns illegal activity or is misleading, whether the asserted governmental interest is substantial, whether the regulation directly advances governmental interests, and whether the regulation in question is more extensive than necessary to advance those interests. See Thompson v. W. States Med. Ctr., 535 U.S. 357, 367 (2002) (articulating modern Central Hudson test). Courts, however, do not consider all expression involving financial transactions commercial speech.

In a trio of cases in the 1980s, the Supreme Court found solicitation from charitable groups was noncommercial speech deserving of the First Amendment’s full protections. In the first of these cases, Schaumburg v. Citizens for a Better Environment, the Court considered a law requiring charities that solicited door to door to dedicate at least seventy-five percent of donations to charitable purposes. 26 444 U.S. 620, 620 (1980). Striking down the law, the Court rejected the Village of Schaumburg’s arguments that canvassing for donations is “purely commercial speech” because charitable solicitors advocate for particular social or political issues as opposed to merely trying to inform economic decisions. 27 Id. at 632. The Court cited New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, a seminal libel case in which the Court treated an advertisement soliciting donations to help aid Civil Rights in the South as fully protected by the First Amendment. Id. at 633 (citing N.Y. Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U.S. 254 (1964)). In subsequent cases, the Court has expanded and affirmed Schaumburg’s protection for solicitation. 28 In Secretary of State of Maryland v. Joseph H. Munson Co., the Court struck down another law mandating percentage requirements for charities, despite the fact that unlike in Schaumberg, the regulation in Munson provided a process for organizations to seek an exemption from the law. 467 U.S. 947, 966–68 (1984). Furthermore, in Riley v. National Federation of the Blind of North Carolina, the Court ruled that even requiring reporting of what percentage of expenditures a charity spent on charitable purposes unduly burdened freedom of speech. 487 U.S. 781, 795 (1988). Despite the fact that solicitation at many times involves commercial elements, 29 A well-known example of commercial elements intermixing with solicitation would be the famous annual sale of cookies to support the Girls Scouts of the USA. See Yum! It’s Time for Girl Scout Cookies!, http://www.girlscouts.org/program/gs_cookies
/find_cookies.asp [http://perma.cc/Y94R-NUAP] (last visited Feb. 2, 2016) (describing Girl Scout Cookie Program). A purchase of Thin Mints likely will involve elements of giving to the nonprofit Girl Scouts of the USA, in addition to simply buying the cookies.
Schaumberg stands for the proposition that the Court will not try to parse out which parts of solicitation involve traditional elements of First Amendment protection and which constitute mere commerce; instead, it will treat all such speech as protected. 30 The Court arguably weakened protection for charitable solicitation in Watchtower Bible & Tract Society of New York, Inc. v. Village of Stratton, where in dicta the Court said if an ordinance requiring permits for door-to-door solicitation applied only to “commercial activities and the solicitation of funds, arguably the ordinance” would not have posed constitutional issues. 536 U.S. 150, 165 (2002). The Court noted, however, that since the ordinance affected “noncommercial” canvassers promoting “causes,” it invoked First Amendment protection, seemingly contradicting Schaumburg. Id. But the Court has not yet made this dictum doctrine, and for now, Schaumburg remains good law. See Henry v. City of Cincinnati, No. C-1-03-509, 2005 WL 1198814, at *6 (S.D. Ohio Apr. 28, 2005) (noting Watchtower did not overturn Schaumburg).

2. The Content-Based and Content-Neutral Distinction. — Protected speech is not entirely immune from regulation. The Court interprets the First Amendment to generally prohibit any laws that regulate or restrict “expression because of its message, its ideas, its subject matter, or its content.” 31 Police Dep’t v. Mosley, 408 U.S. 92, 95 (1972). Therefore, an often-dispositive facet of First Amendment analysis is whether the law in question is content based and contingent on what the expression says or content neutral and agnostic to the message conveyed. 32 See Kathleen M. Sullivan & Noah Feldman, Constitutional Law 1112 (18th ed. 2013) (describing distinction between content-based and content-neutral laws as “crucial”); Kagan, supra note 24, at 443 (“The distinction between content-based and content-neutral regulations of speech serves as the keystone of First Amendment law.”).

Courts subject laws that discriminate on the basis of content to strict scrutiny. 33 See Mosley, 408 U.S. at 98–99 (explaining laws that discriminate between kinds of picketing “must be tailored to serve a substantial government interest”). For a law to survive this exacting test, a court must find that the regulation serves a “compelling state interest” and “is narrowly drawn to achieve that end.” 34 Perry Educ. Ass’n v. Perry Local Educators’ Ass’n, 460 U.S. 37, 45 (1983). Courts define narrowly tailored as a “least restrictive means” test. 35 See Sable Commc’ns. of Cal., Inc. v. FCC, 492 U.S. 115, 126 (1989) (“The Government may, however, regulate the content of constitutionally protected speech in order to promote a compelling interest if it chooses the least restrictive means to further the articulated interest.”). Thus, if the government could accomplish its interest in any other way than a content-based regulation on speech, the law fails strict scrutiny and is unconstitutional. 36 See, e.g., Boos v. Barry, 485 U.S. 312, 329 (1998) (striking down law creating buffer zone around embassies because “less restrictive alternative” existed to protect foreign dignitaries); see also Simon & Schuster, Inc. v. Members of N.Y. State Crime Victims Bd., 502 U.S. 105, 119–20 (1991) (finding law preventing criminals from profiting from memoirs of their exploits unconstitutional because while state has compelling interest in preventing wrongdoers from profiting from crimes, law was not narrowly tailored because government had no justification for treating criminals’ assets differently).

Due to the stringent requirements of the strict scrutiny test, content-based laws are nearly per se considered illegal. 37 See United States v. Playboy Entm’t Grp., 529 U.S. 803, 818 (2000) (“It is rare that a regulation restricting speech because of its content will ever be permissible.”); Barry P. McDonald, Speech and Distrust: Rethinking the Content Approach to Protecting the Freedom of Expression, 81 Notre Dame L. Rev. 1347, 1351 (2006) (noting laws deemed content based are “categorically invalidated”). The Court has nonethe­less shown some willingness to uphold a content-based law when balancing another fundamental right, such as the right to vote. 38 See, e.g., Burson v. Freeman, 504 U.S. 191, 211 (1992) (upholding law prohibiting campaign materials near polling places as “rare case” in which “law survives strict scrutiny”). Still, determining the content-neutral or content-based distinction remains critically important and dispositive in nearly all cases.

Making the determination of what laws fall into each category has traditionally been murky. Academics routinely have denounced the byzantine and inconsistent manner courts determine whether a regulation discriminates against the content of speech. 39 See Case Comment, McCullen v. Coakley, 128 Harv. L. Rev. 221, 226 (2014) [hereinafter Case Comment, McCullen] (“Perhaps no branch of the Supreme Court’s constitutional jurisprudence has been so roundly and routinely criticized as that concerning content neutrality.”). This Note explores how Reed v. Town of Gilbert 40 135 S. Ct. 2218 (2015). articulates a new standard for determining content neutrality in section II.C. 41 See infra section II.C (discussing Reed).

3. Intermediate Scrutiny Test. — Courts group content-neutral laws into two categories: those that place an incidental burden on speech and those that merely regulate the time, place, and manner of speech. 42 See Sullivan & Feldman, supra note 32, at 1128–29 (discussing content-neutral tests). Unlike content-based laws, which require strict scrutiny, these tests employ “intermediate scrutiny” to determine if the regulation violates the First Amendment. 43 Id.

Courts use a test from United States v. O’Brien 44 391 U.S. 367 (1968). to analyze laws that primarily regulate conduct but also place burdens on speech. In O’Brien, a protester faced charges for destroying his draft card during a protest of the Vietnam War. 45 Id. at 369. The Court upheld the prohibition on burning draft cards after evaluating the law under what is now referred to as the O’Brien test:

[A] government regulation is sufficiently justified if it is within the constitutional power of the Government; if it furthers an important or substantial governmental interest; if the governmental interest is unrelated to the suppression of free expression; and if the incidental restriction on alleged First Amendment freedoms is no greater than is essential to the furtherance of that interest. 46 Id. at 377.

O’Brien’s progeny have further clarified this four-part analysis. In particular, the Court in Ward v. Rock Against Racism made clear that O’Brien’s fourth prong—that burdens on speech be “no greater than essential”—does not equate to the “least restrictive means” requirement of strict scrutiny. 47 Ward v. Rock Against Racism, 491 U.S. 781, 798–99 (1989). Ward concerned a time, place, and manner test, but at that point in time the Court had rolled the O’Brien and time, place, and manner tests into one intermediate scrutiny test. See infra note 53 and accompanying text (discussing blending of intermediate scrutiny tests). Instead, intermediate scrutiny requires that the law in question is “not substantially broader than necessary to achieve the government’s interest.” 48 Id. at 799–800.

The second category of content-neutral laws regulates speech directly but does so irrespective of its content. 49 See Sullivan & Feldman, supra note 32, at 1120 (defining “time, place and manner” restrictions). The law in Ward—an ordinance that regulated decibel levels in a Central Park band shell—serves as an exemplar for such a “time, place and manner” law. 50 See Ward, 491 U.S. at 784. The Court in Ward applied a test requiring the regulation to be “justified without reference to the content of the regulated speech,” to be “narrowly tailored to serve a significant governmental interest,” and to “leave open ample alternative channels for communication.” 51 Id. at 791 (quoting Clark v. Cmty. for Creative Non-Violence, 468 U.S. 288, 293 (1984)).

The major difference between the tests in O’Brien and Ward is the requirement in the latter that regulations allow “ample alternative channels” for the expression. 52 Id. Ward stated there was “little, if any” difference between the two tests. 53 Id. at 797–98 (quoting Clark, 468 U.S. at 298). As a result, some scholars view the tests as virtually identical, 54 See, e.g., James M. McGoldrick, Jr., Symbolic Speech: A Message from Mind to Mind, 61 Okla. L. Rev. 1, 31 (2008) (describing O’Brien and time, place, and manner test as “essentially interchangeable”). while others believe that the additional requirement of alternative communications for the time, place, and manner test still affects courtroom outcomes. 55 See, e.g., Ashutosh Bhagwat, The Test that Ate Everything: Intermediate Scrutiny in First Amendment Jurisprudence, 2007 U. Ill. L. Rev. 783, 792 (“[I]n applying O’Brien the Court does not seem inclined to enforce an ‘ample alternative channels of communication’ requirement . . . .”). In analyzing panhandling cases, this Note will not attempt to synthesize the difference between these two tests but will simply recognize which intermediate scrutiny test the court in question applied.

4. Public Forum Doctrine. — In summarizing First Amendment doctrine, this Note has made an important assumption: The laws regulating First Amendment expression do so in public forums. As Justice Owen Roberts noted in the case of Hague v. Committee for Industrial Organization, public forums such as streets and parks serve a crucial function for “purposes of assembly, communicating thoughts between citizens and discussing public questions.” 56 307 U.S. 496, 515 (1939). Thus, courts feel their use of the exacting tests for both content-neutral and content-based laws is justified when such laws seek to regulate speech in these forums. 57 See Snyder v. Phelps, 131 S. Ct. 1207, 1218 (2011) (noting public forums have “‘special position in terms of First Amendment protection’” due to their importance for public assembly and debate (quoting United States v. Grace, 461 U.S. 171, 180 (1983))).

In addition to “traditional” public forums such as streets and parks, courts also recognize designated public forums: private property that the government has opened for expression. 58 See Perry Educ. Ass’n v. Perry Local Educators’ Ass’n., 460 U.S. 37, 45 (1983) (defining designated public forums as “public property which the State has opened for use by the public as a place for expressive activity”); see also Kent Greenawalt, Viewpoints from Olympus, 96 Colum. L. Rev. 697, 699 n.10 (1996) (noting distinction between public and limited public forums). Examples of designated public forums include university meeting places 59 See Widmar v. Vincent, 454 U.S. 263, 267–68 (1981) (deciding University of Missouri, by accommodating student meetings, “created a forum generally open for use by student groups”). and municipal theaters. 60 See Se. Promotions, Ltd. v. Conrad, 420 U.S. 546, 555 (1975) (holding municipal theaters were “public forums designed for and dedicated to expressive activities”). While nothing compels governments to create designated public forums, once the state has designated property for expression, courts will analyze speech regulations under the same tests employed for traditional public forums. 61 See Perry Educ. Ass’n, 460 U.S. at 46 (“Although a State is not required to indefinitely retain the open character of [a designated public forum], as long as it does so it is bound by the same standards as apply in a traditional public forum.”).

Not all property owned by the government is a public forum or designated public forum. 62 See U.S. Postal Serv. v. Council of Greenburg Civic Ass’ns, 453 U.S. 114, 129 (1981) (noting “First Amendment does not guarantee access to property simply because it is owned or controlled by the government”). Courts treat a government forum as nonpublic if the government excludes the public from its property or opens areas to the public for reasons independent of expression—such as commercial activities or trade. 63 See United States v. Kokinda, 497 U.S. 720, 725 (1990) (noting forums become nonpublic when government acts as operator or manager as opposed to lawmaker). Examples include state fairgrounds 64 See Heffron v. Int’l Soc’y for Krishna Consciousness, Inc., 452 U.S. 640, 654–55 (1981) (holding Minnesota state fairgrounds are nonpublic forum). and airports, where the government allows the general public to use facilities for the respective purposes of commerce and transportation. 65 See, e.g., Int’l Soc’y for Krishna Consciousness, Inc. v. Lee, 505 U.S. 672, 681–83 (1992) (holding New York metropolitan area airports to be limited public forums). Courts evaluate regulation of speech in these areas under a far more lenient standard 66 Id. at 679 (noting regulations of nonpublic forums “need only be reasonable, as long as the regulation is not an effort to suppress the speaker’s activity due to disagreement with the speaker’s view”). that asks if the regulation was “reasonable in light of the purpose which the forum at issue serves.” 67 Perry Educ. Ass’n v. Perry Local Educators’ Ass’n, 460 U.S. 37, 49 (1983). Unlike strict or intermediate scrutiny, this reasonableness test does not require narrow tailoring or a compelling governmental interest. 68 Cornelius v. NAACP Legal Def. & Educ. Fund, Inc., 473 U.S. 788, 806 (1985). Like the distinction between content-based and content-neutral speech, deciding the forum has an outsized impact on whether a law will pass constitutional muster. First Amendment doctrine represents a complex framework of overlapping tests that courts use to ascertain which speech is protected and if speech is protected, whether or not a law regulates the speech in a manner consistent with the Constitution.

B. Captive Audience Doctrine

As the constitutionality of the noise-control ordinance at issue in Ward demonstrates, privacy and tranquility of citizens subjected to speech can be a compelling interest. 69 See supra notes 49–51 and accompanying text (discussing facts of Ward). Despite this holding, First Amendment doctrine usually does not protect those subjected to speech they dislike in public forums because individuals can simply choose to walk away and not listen. 70 See, e.g., Bolger v. Young’s Drug Prods. Corp., 463 U.S. 60, 72 (1983) (noting government cannot decide to prohibit mailing of potentially offensive materials because such missives can easily be discarded); Cohen v. California, 403 U.S. 15, 21 (1971) (noting onlookers could simply avert eyes from jacket displaying provocative swear word to protest conscription). A problem arises, however, when people cannot avoid expression—when they are captive to speech they find disturbing or unsettling.

Courts usually apply the First Amendment as an active right to both speak and listen (or read or watch). Yet embedded in the freedom of speech is a right not to speak 71 See, e.g., W. Va. Bd. of Educ. v. Barnette, 319 U.S. 624, 642 (1943) (ruling school officials cannot compel students to recite Pledge of Allegiance and stating “no official, high or petty, can prescribe what shall be orthodox in politics, nationalism, religion, or other matters of opinion or force citizens to confess by word or act their faith therein”). and a right not to listen. As one commentator has stated: “[C]ompulsion to listen is the hallmark of a totalitarian society.” 72 Thomas I. Emerson, The Affirmative Side of the First Amendment, 15 Ga. L. Rev. 795, 833 (1981). Indeed, one of the more terrifying aspects of George Orwell’s infamous repressive regime depicted in 1984 was television screens in every apartment that could never be turned off. See George Orwell, 1984, at 2 (1949). This right not to listen is often referred to as the captive audience doctrine. 73 See William E. Lee, The Unwilling Listener: Hill v. Colorado’s Chilling Effect on Unorthodox Speech, 35 U.C. Davis L. Rev. 387, 404 (2002) (“A captive audience exists where listeners are either unable to avoid exposure to speech or avoidance entails a significant burden.”). It reaches its apex in one’s residence. The Court noted “[t]he right to avoid unwelcome speech has special force in the privacy of the home.” 74 Hill v. Colorado, 530 U.S. 703, 717 (2000) (citing Rowan v. U.S. Post Office Dep’t, 397 U.S. 728, 738 (1970)). The Court has upheld laws that allow residents to direct the Post Office not to send advertisements to their domiciles 75 Rowan, 397 U.S. at 738 (“That we are often ‘captives’ outside the sanctuary of the home and subject to objectionable speech and other sound does not mean we must be captives everywhere. The asserted right of a mailer, we repeat, stops at the outer boundary of every person’s domain.” (citing Pub. Utils. Comm’n v. Pollak, 343 U.S. 451 (1952))); see also Nat’l Fed’n of the Blind v. FTC, 420 F.3d 331, 340, 350–51 (4th Cir. 2005) (upholding law creating “do not call” list that allows people to opt out of telephone solicitations). and municipal ordinances preventing picketing around personal residences. 76 Frisby v. Schultz, 487 U.S. 474, 487 (1988) (“The First Amendment permits the government to prohibit offensive speech as intrusive when the ‘captive’ audience cannot avoid the objectionable speech.”).

How far the right to avoid speech extends beyond the home—and the government’s compelling interest in protecting that right—is unclear. 77 Some scholars argue the captive audience doctrine should apply to the workplace and protect employees from an employer who insists on propagating political views or creates a hostile work environment. See Roger C. Hartley, Freedom Not to Listen: A Constitutional Analysis of Compulsory Indoctrination Through Workplace Captive Audience Meetings, 31 Berkeley J. Emp. & Lab. L. 65, 90–91 (2010) (arguing for application of captive audience doctrine to workplace); see also id. at 91 n.143 (listing scholars who argue for some application of captive audience doctrine to workplace setting). The Court has never applied the right in this context, however, and Professor Eugene Volokh argues doing so would violate important First Amendment principles. See Eugene Volokh, Freedom of Speech and Workplace Harassment, 39 UCLA L. Rev. 1791, 1840 (1992) (arguing applying captive audience doctrine to workplace would create slippery slope because “if captivity consists of an inability to avoid offensive speech, in today’s society we are all ‘captive’ to profanity”). The Supreme Court has extended the doctrine at least once in the limited case of public transportation. In Lehman v. Shaker Heights, the Court upheld Shaker Heights’s refusal to allow a political candidate to run an advertisement on public buses in part because bus passengers were members of a captive audience. 78 418 U.S. 298, 303–04 (1974). In his concurrence Justice Douglas went further, contending that even commercial advertisements on a public bus might be unconstitutional due to the captive nature of passengers. See id. at 307–08 (Douglas, J., concurring in the judgment) (“Commercial advertisements may be as offensive and intrusive to captive audiences as any political message.”). Justice Douglas also expressed this view in Public Utilities Commission v. Pollak, a case decided more than twenty years before Lehman. Pollak, 343 U.S. at 467–69 (Douglas, J., dissenting). In that case, Justice Douglas wrote that music played for passengers of streetcars and buses by the Capital Transit Company violated the First Amendment because “the man on the streetcar has no choice but to sit and listen, or perhaps to sit and to try not to listen” and that “[w]hen we force people to listen to another’s ideas we give the propagandist a powerful weapon.” Id. at 468–69. Courts, however, have not applied the captive audience doctrine when transit authorities’ allowance of both political and commercial speech creates a designated public forum. 79 See supra notes 56–61 and accompanying text (discussing designated public forums). For example, the Second Circuit has ruled that because the Metropolitan Transportation Authority (MTA) accepts political advertisements, it cannot refuse advertisements due to poten­tially objectionable content. 80 See N.Y. Magazine v. Metro. Transp. Auth., 136 F.3d 123, 125–26, 130 (2d Cir. 1998) (holding MTA could not refuse New York Magazine advertisement because it contained name of Mayor Rudolph Giuliani). The Southern District of New York has applied the rule even to advertisements many would find extremely inflammatory, without considering any captive audience rights of subway passengers. 81 See Am. Freedom Def. Initiative v. Metro. Transp. Auth., 880 F. Supp. 2d. 456, 477–78 (S.D.N.Y. 2012) (holding MTA could not refuse to display pro-Israeli advertisement that MTA felt was demeaning to Muslims).

Furthermore, the captive audience doctrine has a very limited function outside the home. In Erznoznik v. City of Jacksonville, while acknowledging the “privacy rights” of captive audiences, the Court struck down an ordinance preventing the showing of nudity at drive-in movie theaters visible from a public place due to concerns about government censorship. 82 See 422 U.S. 205, 208–12, 217 (1975) (“Thus, we conclude that the limited privacy interest of persons on the public streets cannot justify this censorship of otherwise protected speech on the basis of its content.”). Justice Douglas wrote a short concurrence where he identified the case as one with a captive audience but still found the ordinance unconstitutional. Id. at 218 (Douglas, J., concurring in the judgment).

Despite the doctrine’s limitations, the Court has historically shown interest in applying the captive audience framework to the healthcare context. In Hill v. Colorado, the Court upheld a law designed to protect people near abortion clinics from protesters by creating eight-foot “buffer zones” around those near health care facilities where protesters could not approach without consent. 83 530 U.S. 703, 707–08 (2000) (describing statute). Writing for the Court, Justice Stevens applied the captive audience doctrine to those seeking health-care, carving out a governmental interest to protect the ability of one to go from their house to a healthcare facility without having to enter a “confrontational setting[].” 84 Id. at 717.

This ruling in Hill has come under question after another abortion-protest case: the recent decision of McCullen v. Coakley. 85 134 S. Ct. 2518 (2014). In McCullen, Chief Justice Roberts discussed being a captive audience not as a First Amendment violation but rather a virtuous element of the marketplace of ideas:

It is no accident that public streets and sidewalks have developed as venues for the exchange of ideas. Even today, they remain one of the few places where a speaker can be confident that he is not simply preaching to the choir. With respect to other means of communication, an individual confronted with an uncomfortable message can always turn the page, change the channel, or leave the Web site. Not so on public streets and sidewalks. There, a listener often encounters speech he might otherwise tune out. In light of the First Amendment’s purpose “to preserve an uninhibited marketplace of ideas in which truth will ultimately prevail” this aspect of traditional public forums is a virtue, not a vice. 86 Id. at 2529 (quoting FCC v. League of Women Voters of Cal., 468 U.S. 364, 377 (1984)).

Whether this holding applies in the panhandling context, in particular the aggressive panhandling context, will be discussed later in section III.B.

II. Panhandling Regulations and Jurisprudence

Part I discussed the First Amendment doctrinal frameworks; this Part discusses how appellate courts have applied those frameworks to panhandling cases. It also discusses the recent case of Reed v. Town of Gilbert 87 135 S. Ct. 2218 (2015). and its potential effects on panhandling laws. Section II.A argues that panhandling is protected First Amendment speech. Section II.B discusses how appellate courts have interpreted First Amendment doctrine as applied to panhandling cases and shows that the current content-based analysis of panhandling creates doctrinal difficulties. Section II.C notes how Reed altered existing frameworks for determining whether speech regulations are content-based or content-neutral.

A. Panhandling Is Protected Speech

While the Supreme Court has made clear that the First Amendment protects soliciting donations for charities, 88 See supra notes 26–28 and accompanying text (discussing charitable solicitation cases). Justice Rehnquist in his dissent in Schaumburg, however, argued that governments should be able to distinguish valid charities from “panhandlers, profiteers and peddlers.” See Vill. of Schaumburg v. Citizens for a Better Env’t, 444 U.S. 620, 644 (1980) (Rehnquist, J., dissenting). it has remained silent on the issue of whether personal solicitation or panhandling falls under such protections. 89 See Speet v. Schuette, 726 F.3d 867, 874 (6th Cir. 2013) (“[T]he United States Supreme Court has not . . . directly decided the question of whether the First Amendment protects soliciting alms when done by an individual . . . .”). This section argues panhandling now enjoys—and should enjoy—First Amendment protection. It begins by rejecting alternative methods of treating panhandling and then discusses the current de facto consensus among appellate courts that panhandling is protected speech.

1. Alternatives to Protected Speech. — It is easy to conceive of potential classifications for panhandling other than protected speech. Since panhandling involves an exchange—or a request of an exchange—of goods or currency, one possible paradigm to view panhandling would be commercial speech. 90 See supra note 25 and accompanying text (discussing commercial speech). As most cases now find panhandling to fall under the auspices of Schaumburg, 91 See infra notes 121–129 and accompanying text (noting widespread adoption of panhandling as protected solicitation). courts do not question whether such personal solicitation is “purely commercial” and therefore subject to the Central Hudson test. 92 But see Watchtower Bible & Tract Soc’y of N.Y., Inc. v. Vill. of Stratton, 536 U.S. 150, 151 (2002) (positing that given regulation of “commercial activities and the solicitation of funds, arguably the ordinance” would not violate Constitution). It makes sense that courts would be loath to try to find what panhandling was purely commercial, just like solicitation it would be almost impossible to see where the commercial speech ended and First Amendment speech began. Even in situations where the panhandling has more commercial elements, such as someone who performs a song or washes a windshield in order to help spur donations, it would be impossible to delineate which part of the message is protected solicitation and which is commercial. 93 For an example on parsing out solicitation, see supra note 29 (discussing how selling Girl Scout cookies is both solicitation and commercial speech).

In a 2005 case in the Southern District of Ohio, the City of Cincinnati argued the court should treat panhandling as commercial speech. 94 See Henry v. City of Cincinnati, No. C-1-03-509, 2005 WL 1198814, at *6 (S.D. Ohio Apr. 28, 2005) (discussing Cincinnati’s legal theory in case); see also supra notes 26–27 and accompanying text (discussing Schaumburg). The district court rejected this claim, holding that Schaumburg controlled even for personal solicitations, evincing the widespread con-sensus among the courts that panhandling is not commercial speech. 95 See Henry, 2005 WL 1198814, at *6–7 (“[P]anhandling, like charitable solicitation is more than mere commercial speech.”).

Courts could alternatively analyze panhandling as purely “low value” speech or conduct outside of the First Amendment’s protections. 96 See supra notes 21–24 and accompanying text (discussing expression First Amendment does not protect). The Second Circuit in Young v. New York City Transit Authority 97 903 F.2d 146, 148 (2d Cir. 1990). exemplifies this approach.

In Young the court took up a challenge of the New York City Transportation Authority’s 98 The New York City Transportation Authority is the subsidiary of the MTA in charge of New York City transportation and the subway system. See New York City Transit—History and Chronology, Metropolitan Transportation Authority, http://web. mta.info/nyct/ facts/ffhist.htm [http://perma.cc/T6E7-9G7R] (last visited Feb. 2, 2016). This Note will refer to the authority under the commonly known acronym of its parent corporation: MTA. (MTA’S) longtime ban on panhandling and begging in New York City subway system. 99 903 F.2d at 148. While the Supreme Court in Schaumburg ruled solicitation for charities conveyed important political and economic messages, 100 See supra note 27 and accompanying text (discussing rationale in Schaumburg for protecting charitable solicitation). the Young court noted in dicta that “[t]he only message that we are able to espy as common to all acts of begging is that beggars want to extract money from those whom they accost” and that “[w]hile organized charities serve community interests by enhancing communica­tion and disseminating ideas, the conduct of begging and panhandling in the subway amounts to nothing less than a menace to the common good.” 101 Young, 903 F.2d at 153–54 (emphasis added); id. at 156. Thus, the court argued “common sense tells us that begging is much more ‘conduct’ than it is ‘speech’” and therefore is out­side the First Amendment’s protections. 102 Id. at 153–54.

The Second Circuit, however, declined to declare panhandling unprotected conduct, and despite its dismissive language on pan-handling’s First Amendment value and its determination that the subway system was a nonpublic forum, 103 Id. at 161–62 (“[T]he [M]TA never intended to designate sections of the subway system, including platforms and mezzanines, as a place for begging and panhandling . . . the subway system is not a traditional or designated public forum.”). the court still performed an inter-mediate scrutiny O’Brien analysis as well as a “time, manner and place” test “arguendo.” 104 See id. at 157–61 (applying intermediate scrutiny tests to prohibition of panhandling in subway cars). Unsurprisingly, the Young court found the MTA’s regulation passed both intermediate scrutiny tests. 105 See id. at 161 (“[E]ven if begging and panhandling constitute protected expressive conduct, which is in serious doubt, we hold that the regulation at issue more than satisfies the O’Brien standard . . . .”); see also id. at 160 (holding regulation allowed for “‘ample alternatives of communication’” (quoting Ward v. Rock Against Racism, 491 U.S. 781, 802 (1989))). As the next section demonstrates, this holding proved to be ephemeral.

2. The Loper Approach: Panhandling as Protected Speech. — The Second Circuit’s view of panhandling as conduct or low-value speech from Young did not last long: In an influential and oft-cited opinion, 106 See infra notes 122–126 and accompanying text (discussing explicit adoption of Loper’s holding by numerous appellate courts). the court shifted its position in Loper v. New York City Police Department three years later, beginning the process of a widespread recognition among federal courts that panhandling deserves constitutional protection. 107 999 F.2d 699 (2d Cir. 1993). In Loper, the Second Circuit struck down a law punishing loitering with the intent to panhandle. 108 Id. at 701. In sharp contrast to Young, 109 See Young, 903 F.2d at 153–54 (stating panhandling does not possess sufficient communicative elements to warrant First Amendment protection); see also supra notes 102–105 and accompanying text (discussing Young). the Loper court defined begging as “communicative activity,” finding the loitering statute content neutral. 110 Loper, 999 F.2d at 704.

Unlike Young, where the court applied intermediate scrutiny only in arguendo, the Loper court believed panhandling fell under the First Amendment’s protection as solicitation as established in Schaumburg. 111 See supra notes 26–30 and accompanying text (discussing charitable-solicitation cases). The Loper court went as far as stating that there is “little difference between those who solicit for organized charities and those who solicit for themselves . . . .” 112 Loper, 999 F.2d at 704. This sentiment is very similar to the dissent in Young. See Young, 903 F.2d at 164 (Meskill, J., dissenting) (expressing belief that there exists no “leg-ally justifiable distinction” between solicitation for personal reasons and soliciting for charitable organizations). Accordingly, the Loper court analyzed the law under the time, place, and manner test and ruled that while banning panhandling in the subway still allowed beggars to communicate above ground, a ban on all panhandling would foreclose all alternative means of communication. 113 Loper, 999 F.2d at 705 (“[T]otal prohibition on begging in the city streets imposed by the statute cannot be characterized as . . . merely incidental . . . .”). One argument to justify the public-forum doctrine is that it protects those who require public spaces to communicate their message because traditional means of getting public attention is prohibitively expensive. See Geoffrey R. Stone, Content Regulation and the First Amendment, 25 Wm. & Mary L. Rev. 189, 219 (1983). While not explicitly mentioned in Loper, this argument certainly strengthens the court’s ruling. Distinguishing the case from Young by noting that the statute in Loper regulated the traditional public forums of streets and parks while the MTA ban in Young only applied to subway cars and their immediate environs, 114 Id. at 703–04. Regulation of free speech in public forums is subject to strict scrutiny and therefore deciding whether the forum is public is often dispositive of the out-come of an O’Brien balancing test. See Police Dep’t v. Mosley, 408 U.S. 92, 98–99 (1972) (noting careful scrutiny needed for public forums). the Second Circuit applied the arguably more regulation-friendly O’Brien test 115 While the Supreme Court has said there is little to no difference between the intermediate scrutiny tests, the O’Brien test does not have a requirement for alternative means of communication, while the time, place, and manner test does. See supra notes 52–55 and accompanying text (noting possible difference). and found the law insufficiently tailored. 116 Loper, 999 F.2d at 705–06 (ruling statutes broader than necessary, thus failing O’Brien test).

Academic work on panhandling supports the Loper court’s argument that panhandling conveys a message deserving of First Amendment protection. Some commentators have pointed out that begging can have First Amendment value for both those who panhandle and for those who are on the receiving end of the solicitation: First, panhandling informs those receiving and witnessing solicitations about societal problems such as homelessness and poverty, either through the words spoken or the mere act of begging itself. 117 See Helen Hershkoff & Adam S. Cohen, Commentary, Begging to Differ: The First Amendment and the Right to Beg, 104 Harv. L. Rev. 896, 898 (1991) (noting begging “provides information about poverty and the lives of poor people”); see also Nancy A. Millich, Compassion Fatigue and the First Amendment: Are the Homeless Constitutional Castaways?, 27 U.C. Davis L. Rev. 255, 275–81 (1994) (arguing begging contributes to public’s awareness of homelessness as problem). This awareness takes on an added import-ance in a democratic society, as information about the existence and prevalence of abject poverty may inform a voter’s choices come Election Day. 118 See Hershkoff & Cohen, supra note 117, at 901–02 (discussing democratic value of begging). On a deeper level, begging may encourage listeners of the speech to evaluate their own feelings about living in a society of homelessness or to fulfill spiritual obligations by giving alms to the needy. 119 See id. at 899–901 (setting forth these arguments as part of what authors call “enlightenment value” of begging); Mark Oppenheimer, The Beggars of Lakewood, N.Y. Times Mag. (Oct. 16, 2014), http://www.nytimes.com/2014/10/19/magazine/the-beggars-of-lakewood.html (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (discussing role of begging and giving alms in ultra–Orthodox Judaism). But see Robert C. Ellickson, Controlling Chronic Misconduct in City Spaces: Of Panhandlers, Skid Rows and Public-Space Zoning, 105 Yale L.J. 1165, 1180–81 (1996) (noting while major religions encourage charity, they also discourage begging and instead emphasize self-help and work ethic). Finally, the act of begging can allow for panhandlers to achieve self-realization by giving them the freedom to express themselves and to express their values about giving to others and society in general. 120 See Hershkoff & Cohen, supra note 117, at 903–04 (discussing self-realization value of begging).

Law professors are not the only ones convinced that constitutional protection for panhandlers is sound. Although never explicitly adopted by the Supreme Court, 121 Loper has had traction with at least Justice Thomas. In a joint dissent with Justice Scalia in a campaign-finance case, Nixon v. Shrink Missouri Government PAC, Justice Thomas approvingly noted that appellate courts have extended the First Amendment to begging and cites. Loper, 528 U.S. 377, 412 & n.2 (2000) (Thomas, J., dissenting). a number of jurisdictions have followed Loper’s determinations that the First Amendment protects personal solicitation. The Fourth, 122 See Reynolds v. Middleton, 779 F.3d 222, 225 (4th Cir. 2015) (“There is no question that panhandling and solicitation of charitable contributions are protected speech.”); Clatterbuck v. City of Charlottesville, 708 F.3d 549, 552–54 (4th Cir. 2013) (ruling “speech and expressive conduct that comprise begging” deserves First Amendment protection and invalidating statute banning panhandling on two streets in downtown Charlottesville). Sixth, 123 See Speet v. Shuette, 726 F.3d 867, 875 (6th Cir. 2013) (striking down Michigan statute criminalizing begging and noting “begging is a form of solicitation that the First Amendment protects”). Seventh, 124 See Gresham v. Pereson, 225 F.3d 899, 904 (7th Cir. 2000) (allowing for regulation of some panhandling activities in Indianapolis but following Loper’s view of little difference between personal solicitation and those for charitable groups). Ninth, 125 See ACLU v. City of Las Vegas, 466 F.3d 784, 792 (9th Cir. 2006) (“It is beyond dispute that solicitation is a form of expression entitled to the same constitutional protections as traditional speech.”). and Eleventh 126 See Smith v. City of Fort Lauderdale, 177 F.3d 954, 955–56 (11th Cir. 1999) (allowing for panhandling regulation on public beaches but noting “[l]ike other charitable solicitation, begging is speech entitled to First Amendment protection”). Circuits have all explicitly adopted Loper’s First Amendment protection for pan­handling. While not adopting Loper’s holding, the First Circuit has also implied a belief that panhandling deserves at least intermediate scru­tiny. 127 See Thayer v. City of Worcester, 755 F.3d 60, 68 (1st Cir. 2014) (Souter, J.) (applying content-neutral, content-based analysis to panhandling regulation), vacated, 135 S. Ct. 2887 (2015). The Massachusetts Supreme Court has also borrowed reasoning from Loper to find First Amendment protections for panhandling. 128 See Benefit v. City of Cambridge, 679 N.E.2d 184, 188 (Mass. 1997) (invalidating law banning unlicensed begging and finding distinction between personal solicitation and solicitation for a charity “not a significant one for First Amendment purposes” (quoting Loper v. N.Y.C. Police Dep’t, 999 F.2d 699, 704 (2d Cir. 1993))). The Young argument that begging is merely conduct, while never explicitly overturned by Loper or any other Supreme Court case, is nonetheless extinct across jurisdictions. 129 For an argument that the Second Circuit should overturn Young, see Jordana Schreiber, Note, Begging Underground? The Constitutionality of Regulations Banning Panhandling in the New York City Subway System, 27 Cardozo L. Rev. 1517, 1518–19 (2006). The widespread and clear consensus among appellate courts across the country is that the First Amendment protects panhandling.

Finally, while not dispositive of a ruling on the issue, the recent decision in Thayer v. City of Worcester 130 135 S. Ct. 2887 (2015). heavily implies the Supreme Court also views panhandling as protected speech, as it remanded the case to be decided in accordance with Reed v. Town of Gilbert, a case clearly concerning speech rather than conduct. 131 Reed v. Town of Gilbert, 135 S. Ct. 2218, 2226–27 (2015) (applying First Amendment jurisprudence concerning speech to regulation of signs). This further evinces that despite the lack of an explicit ruling, it is virtually settled law that panhandling deserves at least some First Amendment protections.

3. Justice Kennedy’s Lee Approach. — Although the First Amendment protects panhandling, it is not altogether clear that the Loper court’s conclusion that courts should not treat panhandling differently than charitable solicitation is correct. A hybrid approach adopted by Justice Kennedy would treat panhandling as a mixture of both conduct and speech. 132 See supra note 112 and accompanying text (discussing Loper’s view that panhandling is no different than other charitable solicitation). This approach, while never adopted by the Supreme Court, remains influential, especially among judges and lawyers attempt­ing to uphold panhandling regulation, and it is still cited by briefs and cases to this day. 133 See, e.g., Petition for Writ of Certiorari at 16–18, City of Springfield v. Norton, No. 15-727, 2015 WL 7831391 (Dec. 1, 2015) (citing Int’l Soc’y for Krishna Consciousness, Inc. v. Lee, 505 U.S. 672 (1992); United States v. Kokinda, 497 U.S. 720 (1990) (Kennedy, J., concurring in the judgment); see also Norton v. City of Springfield, 768 F.3d 713, 715–16 (7th Cir. 2014) (purporting that Justice Kennedy’s opinion in Lee is justification for treating panhandling regulation as content neutral), rev’d, 806 F.3d 411 (7th Cir. 2015); Brief in Opposition to the Petition for a Writ of Certiorari at 12, Thayer v. City of Worcester, 755 F.3d 60 (1st Cir. 2014), vacated,135 S. Ct. 2887 (2015) (mem.) (No. 14-428), 2014 WL 6449706 (same). As discussed in section III.A, however, the decision in Reed to adopt a formalist approach to content neutrality means that this approach is now untenable. 134 See infra section III.A (discussing Reed’s adoption of formalist approach).

Justice Kennedy’s approach is best encapsulated by his concurrence in International Society for Krishna Consciousness, Inc. v. Lee. 135 505 U.S. at 693 (Kennedy, J., concurring in the judgments). Justice Kennedy’s approach also appears in United States v. Kokinda, 497 U.S. at 733–34, 736 (plurality opinion) (discussing solicitation regulation as content neutral); see also id. at 739 (Kennedy, J., concurring in the judgment)(reiterating that regulating in that case was content-neutral). In that case, members of the Hare Krishna sect challenged a ban on charitable solici­tations in and on the sidewalks of airports operated by the Port Authority of New York and New Jersey. 136 Lee, 505 U.S. at 674–75.

The majority opinion found the solicitation protected by the First Amendment but showed far more wariness toward personal solicitation: “[F]ace-to-face solicitation presents risks of duress that are an appropriate target of regulation.” 137 Id. at 684. As panhandling necessarily involves such face-to-face solicitation, 138 See supra notes 17–18 and accompanying text(defining panhandling). it is impossible not to imagine such skepticism applying to panhandling as well. 139 Indeed, Judge Frank Easterbrook applied Lee when analyzing a panhandling regulation in a recent case. See Norton v. City of Springfield, 768 F.3d 713, 715 (7th Cir. 2014), rev’d, 806 F.3d 411 (7th Cir. 2015); see also supra note 133 (discussing citations of Lee in panhandling cases and briefs). It is important to note that since the Court in Lee ruled that New York airports constituted nonpublic forums, the Court employed only a reasonableness test as opposed to strict or intermediate scrutiny. See Lee, 505 U.S. at 684–85 (concluding ban passes reasonableness test under First Amendment); see also supra section I.A.3 (discussing public forum doctrine). Because of this, the effect of the majority opinion in Lee on panhandling in public forums is quite limited.

In a concurrence, Justice Kennedy took the majority’s antipathy toward face-to-face regulation further. Unlike the majority, Justice Kennedy argued airports were public forums and considered the ban on solicitation a content-neutral ban subject to intermediate scrutiny. 140 Lee, 505 U.S. at 698 (Kennedy, J., concurring in the judgments) (“It is of particular importance to recognize that such spaces are public forums because in these days an airport is one of the few government-owned spaces where many persons have extensive contact with other members of the public.”). In applying an intermediate scrutiny test, 141 Justice Kennedy collapsed the O’Brien framework and the time, place, and manner test into an intermediate scrutiny analysis. See id. at 704 (“The confluence of the two tests is well demonstrated by a case like this, where the government regulation at issue can be described with equal accuracy as a regulation of the manner of expression, or as a regulation of conduct with an expressive component.”). however, Justice Kennedy argued that while an ordinance banning the solicitation of all funds would be content based, the regulation in Lee aimed only to regulate immediate request of funds and the physical transfer of money, which he described as “an element of conduct interwoven with otherwise expres­sive solicitation.” 142 Id. at 705. Justice Kennedy then noted the dangers of fraud and duress present with such immediate solicitation of funds, analogizing the law in Lee with regulations on door-to-door salesmen. 143 See id. at 706 (describing FTC’s three-day “cooling-off period” that allows consumers to cancel door-to-door sales (internal quotation marks omitted) (quoting 16 C.F.R. §  429.1 (1992)). Justice Kennedy thus felt the banning of solicitation passed intermediate scrutiny as a closely drawn, compelling governmental interest. Justice Kennedy also believed the regulation allowed for alternative methods of communica­tion because solicitors could request nonimmediate donations. 144 Id. (“[T]he regulation is a content-neutral rule serving a significant government interest.”). Justice Kennedy made a similar argument in another case involving solic­itations on public sidewalks in front of U.S. post offices. See United States v. Kokinda, 497 U.S. 720, 739 (Kennedy, J., concurring in the judgment) (accepting Post Office’s “judgment that in-person solicitation deserves different treatment from alternative forms of solicitation and expression”).

Thus, while Justice Kennedy might disagree with the court in Young that panhandling is merely conduct, he would also disagree with the court in Loper that there is “little difference between those who solicit for organized charities and those who solicit for themselves . . . .” 145 Loper v. N.Y.C. Police Dep’t, 999 F.2d 699, 704 (2d Cir. 1993). Justice Kennedy views panhandling as occupying a space between protected third-party solicitation and conduct unprotected by the First Amendment. 146 See supra note 140 and accompanying text (describing Justice Kennedy’s views on airports as public forums). And because this middle ground involves conduct, regulation of pan­handling is content neutral according to Justice Kennedy’s approach. This Note will discuss the future of this approach with the newly adopted standard for approaching content neutrality in Part III.

So far this Note has discussed panhandling and panhandling regulations as a monolithic concept. As the next section demonstrates, nothing is further from the truth, as panhandling regulations have important differences.

B. Categories of Panhandling Regulation

1. Defining Categories. — While no panhandling regulation is identical, many share significant similarities. This Note proposes a tripartite categorization for analyzing these laws and comparing cases across jurisdictions. First, this section describes each of the three types of panhandling laws. It then discusses how appellate courts have treated each category differently.

The simplest types of panhandling laws are “blanket bans,” laws that completely outlaw panhandling in a city. This was the type of law held unconstitutional in Loper 147 See supra notes 110–113 and accompanying text (discussing Loper). and in the Sixth Circuit’s recent decision in Speet v. Schuette. 148 726 F.3d 867, 870 (6th Cir. 2013) (describing Michigan statute that “crimi­nalize[d] begging”). Blanket bans would also describe a recent failed initiative from the San Antonio police chief, which would fine motorists for giving money to panhandlers. 149 See Arthur, supra note 12 (noting proposal supported by San Antonio Police Chief to criminalize giving money to panhandlers failed due to lack of support from city council).

Next are “aggressive begging” statutes, which regulate the type of begging allowed. These laws became in vogue in the 1990s, as a method for cities to control their panhandling “problems” without running afoul of potential constitutional problems. 150 See, e.g., Robert Teir, Maintaining Safety and Civility in Public Spaces: A Constitutional Approach to Aggressive Begging, 54 La. L. Rev. 285, 333–37 (1993) (advo­cating for aggressive-begging laws and offering model statutes); Kent S. Scheidegger, Criminal Justice Legal Found, A Guide to Regulating Panhandling, 10–11 (1993), http://www.cjlf.org/publications/RegulatePanhandling.pdf [http://perma.cc/NU64-QPXB] (observing “[p]rohibition of aggressive or fraudulent panhandling easily meets [time, place, and manner] test”). Even more traditionally liberal institutions saw these laws as a happy medium between blanket bans and anarchy, 151 See Editorial, No’ to Aggressive Panhandlers, N.Y. Times (July 5, 1996), http:// www.nytimes.com/1996/07/05/opinion/no-to-aggressive-panhandlers.html (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (expressing New York Times editorial board’s support of New York aggressive-begging law). and they became popular with many cities, including New York City. 152 See Clifford J. Levy, Council Approves Restrictions on Beggars, N.Y. Times (Sept. 12, 1996), http://www.nytimes.com/1996/09/12/nyregion/council-approves-restrictions-on-beggars.html (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (describing New York City Council’s decision to enact aggressive-begging law and how law was “modeled after similar measures in other cities”). Unlike blanket bans, aggressive-begging statutes only outlaw panhandling seen as “aggressive.” But what “aggressive” means is not lim­ited to the word’s plain meaning, and many aggressive-begging laws give panhandlers a very short leash. New York City’s statute is typical, banning aggressive behavior ranging from causing a reasonable person to fear bodily harm to a mere suffering of “unreasonable inconvenience, annoyance or alarm.” 153 N.Y.C. Administrative Code § 10-136 (LEXIS through March 2015). Unsurprisingly, panhandlers are often not sure when their conduct crosses the line and could cause reasonable fear in another person. See Tatiana Schlossberg, What Elmo and Spidey Want You to Know: They Have Rights, N.Y. Times (Aug. 19, 2014), http://www.nytimes.com/2014/08/20/nyregion/seeking-respect-from-police-times-square-mascots-form-alliance.html (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (“The laws creating the differences between [aggressive and non­aggressive] solicitation are fuzzy at best.”). For an argument that bans on conduct that causes alarm or annoyance in others could sweep in large amounts of begging due to predisposed cognitive biases towards the indigent, see Sara K. Rankin, The Influence of Exile, 76 Md. L. Rev (forthcoming 2016) (manuscript at 36), http://papers.ssrn.com/ abstract=2754254 (on file with the Columbia Law Review). Other prohibited behavior includes begging within ten feet of an ATM machine, approaching vehicles, and obstruct­ing traffic in such a way that pedestrians or vehicles avoid the beggar. 154 N.Y.C. Administrative Code § 10-136.

Other aggressive-begging statutes contain even more restrictions. The City of Worcester enacted a law banning soliciting for donations after sundown and begging from those sitting at a sidewalk café or waiting in line. 155 See Thayer v. City of Worcester, 755 F.3d 60, 64–65 (1st Cir. 2014) (Souter, J.) (describing Worcester statute), vacated, 135 S. Ct. 2887 (2015) (mem.). Similarly, an Indianapolis law classified begging at night, using profanity, following people who walk away, or panhandling in a group of two or more persons as aggressive. 156 See Gresham v. Peterson, 225 F.3d 899, 901–02 (7th Cir. 2000) (describing Indianapolis statute).

Finally, “location bans” outlaw panhandling in certain areas of the city, similar to the subway ban in Young. 157 See supra notes 98–99 (discussing law at issue in Young). Unlike in Young, most location-based bans apply not to unique transportation facilities but to commercial thoroughfares or areas known for tourism. For example, Charlottesville, Virginia, banned begging on two downtown streets, 158 See Clatterbuck v. City of Charlottesville, 708 F.3d 549, 551–52 (4th Cir. 2013) (describing relevant statute). Las Vegas outlawed panhandling in its downtown area in an effort to increase tourism, 159 See ACLU v. City of Las Vegas, 466 F.3d 784, 787–89 (9th Cir. 2006) (describing Las Vegas statute and aspirations of turning relevant area into tourist destination). Henrico County, Virginia, banned panhandling on its roadways 160 See Reynolds v. Middleton, 779 F.3d 222, 224 (4th Cir. 2015) (describing ordinance). and Fort Lauderdale banned panhandling on public beaches. 161 See Smith v. City of Fort Lauderdale, 177 F.3d 954, 955–56 (11th Cir. 1999) (describing statute and importance of public beach to Fort Lauderdale tourism industry). Sometimes location-based laws regulate rather than outright ban panhandling: Springfield, Illinois, enacted such a law in its downtown 162 Norton v. City of Springfield, 806 F.3d 411, 412 (7th Cir. 2015) (discussing Springfield panhandling law). —a center for Lincoln-related tourism 163 Planning a Visit?, Abraham Lincoln Presidential Library & Museum, http://www. lincolnlibraryandmuseum.com/lincoln-tour.htm [http://perma.cc/FX5A-M4DQ] (last visited Feb. 3, 2016) (noting Lincoln Library’s location in Springfield Historic District near state capitol). —as did Seattle, which regulated street performers at Seattle Center, a popular park and home of the Space Needle. 164 See Berger v. City of Seattle, 569 F.3d 1029, 1035–37 (9th Cir. 2009) (en banc) (describing rule and Seattle Center). Critics of location-based regulation charge that banning panhandling in well-trafficked areas is akin to banning panhandling outright, as populated public areas are the only areas where a beggar can profit from his or her solicitations. 165 See Nat’l Law Ctr. on Homelessness & Poverty, No Safe Place: The Criminalization of Homelessness in U.S. Cities 21 (2014), http://www.nlchp.org/ documents/No_Safe_Place [http://perma.cc/Q88T-UE63] (noting impact of location-based bans “can be as great as that of a city-wide ban . . . because commercial and tourist districts . . . are often the only places where homeless people have regular access to passersby and potential donors”).

While the categories are not rigid and many laws exhibit characteris­tics of multiple categories, this categorization allows for a useful framework to discuss and compare different panhandling regulations. It is especially important to distinguish different categories, because as the next section and Part III discuss, blanket and location bans historically have run afoul of intermediate scrutiny tailoring requirements, while aggressive-panhandling bans have more problems with content neutral­ity. As discussed in section II.C and Part III, however, under the new framework of Reed v. Town of Gilbert, 166 135 S. Ct. 2218 (2015). current doctrine treats all of these categories as content-based laws.

2. Differing Appellate Treatment for Differing Panhandling Laws. — Using the tripartite categorization of panhandling laws shows a pattern in how courts have treated such laws. Few cases involve blanket bans, most likely because drafters of ordinances fear such laws will not survive courtroom challenges. 167 See supra notes 150–154 and accompanying text (noting proponents of panhandling laws advocating for more tailored statutes in order to avoid constitutional issues). It is telling that in the recent case of Thayer v. City of Worcester, the city’s lawyers conceded that courts often find blanket bans and location bans with large areas unconstitutional, while attesting to the constitutionality of targeted location bans and aggressive-panhandling bans. 168 See Brief in Opposition to the Petition for a Writ of Certiorari at 22–23, Thayer v. City of Worcester, 755 F.3d 60 (1st Cir. 2014), vacated, 135 S. Ct. 2887 (2015) (mem.) (No. 14-428), 2014 WL 6449706 (arguing “First Circuit properly determined that the Worcester Ordinances are content-neutral, as they are not a broad ban on panhandling or solicitation”).

a. Location and Blanket Bans. — In the one federal appellate court case considering a blanket ban after Loper, the Sixth Circuit ruled that the ban violated the Constitution. 169 See Speet v. Schuette, 726 F.3d 867, 870, 880 (6th Cir. 2013) (holding “anti-begging ordinance” that makes it illegal to beg in public place “violates the First Amendment”). Because the case involved a facial challenge, the Sixth Circuit reached its conclusion using an overbreadth analysis. 170 See id. at 872–73. The overbreadth doctrine invalidates a law that unnecessarily includes substantial amounts of legitimate protected speech in its attempt to satisfy its stated interest. See Sullivan & Feldman, supra note 32, at 1292–93 (noting relationship between facial challenges and vagueness and overbreadth). The recent case of United States v. Stevens illustrates this concept: The Supreme Court invalidated a law proscribing video recordings of animal cruelty because the statute could apply to videos protected by the First Amendment, such as those depicting hunting and religious ceremonies. 559 U.S. 460, 473 (2010) (describing overbreadth doctrine). Due to the overbreadth doctrine’s scope in invalidating laws, courts are cautious in its application. See United States v. Williams, 553 U.S. 285, 293 (2008) (noting overbreadth is “‘strong medicine’ that is not to be ‘casually employed’” (quoting L.A. Police Dep’t v. United Reporting Publ’g Corp., 528 U.S. 32, 39 (1999))). The court also described the regulation as content based, because it distinguished between panhandling and other forms of solic­itation. 171 See Speet, 726 F.3d at 870 (describing “Michigan’s anti-begging statute” as discriminating against forms of solicitation “based on content”). This went further than even the Second Circuit in Loper, which instead applied intermediate scrutiny to what that court felt was a content-neutral law. 172 See supra note 110 and accompanying text (discussing Loper’s treatment of panhandling ban as content neutral). Curiously, the Sixth Circuit also implied a regula­tion of panhandling—perhaps an anti-aggressive-begging statute—might pass muster if it held “due regard” for First Amendment inter­ests. 173 See Speet, 726 F.3d at 880 (stating “Michigan may regulate begging” but only if respecting free-speech values that begging contains). Other than a clearly unconstitutional act banning all solicitation, it is impossible to imagine a panhandling regulation that could be more content neutral. 174 See supra section II.C (discussing recent change in content-based determinations). It is important to note that the government would also be powerless to enact a law banning all solicitation in a public forum due to the holding in Schaumburg. See supra notes 26–28 and accompanying text (discussing charitable-solicitation cases). In one case, United States v. Kokinda, a plurality of the Court held a restriction on all solicitation around U.S. post offices was content neutral. 497 U.S. 720, 736–37 (1990) (plurality opinion) (O’Connor, J.). This case, like Lee, rested on determining the area was a nonpublic forum and therefore does not conflict with Schaumburg’s holding. See id. at 730 (holding post offices to be nonpublic forums).

The Sixth Circuit’s descriptions of the ban in that case might have been dicta, but in considering location bans, other circuits have held begging bans unconstitutional for similar reasons. In considering a ban on panhandling in downtown Charlottesville, the Fourth Circuit ruled:

The Ordinance plainly distinguishes between types of solicita­tions on its face. Whether the Ordinance is violated turns solely on the nature or content of the solicitor’s speech: it prohibits solicitations that request immediate donations of things of value, while allowing other types of solicitations, such as those that request future donations, or those that request things which may have no “value”—a signature or a kind word, perhaps. 175 Clatterbuck v. City of Charlottesville, 708 F.3d 549, 556, 559 (4th Cir. 2013), abrogated by Cent. Radio Co. v. City of Norfolk, 811 F.3d 625 (4th Cir. 2016). For more discussion of Clatterbuck, see infra notes 211–212 and accompanying text.

The Court went on to invalidate the law using a strict scrutiny standard. 176 Clatterbuck, 708 F.3d at 560 (finding statute not “least restrictive means” and therefore failing strict scrutiny).

Similar to the Fourth Circuit, the Ninth Circuit found a location ban on panhandling in downtown Las Vegas content based because it treated solicitation for immediate funds differently. 177 See ACLU of Nev. v. City of Las Vegas, 466 F.3d 784, 787–88, 794 (9th Cir. 2006) (“Even if this distinction is innocuous or eminently reasonable, it is still a content-based distinction because it ‘singles out certain speech for differential treatment based on the idea expressed.’”(quoting Foti v. City of Menlo Park, 146 F.3d 629, 636 n.7 (9th Cir. 1998))). Blanket bans and large location bans have all but disappeared after Loper due to their lack of tailoring. 178 See supra section II.B.1 (defining categories of panhandling regulation). Some more limited location bans do exist, 179 See, e.g., Smith v. City of Fort Lauderdale, 177 F.3d 954, 956 (11th Cir. 1999) (upholding panhandling ban for Fort Lauderdale Beach). although Reed will likely change that in the future. 180 See supra section II.A (discussing panhandling as protected speech).

b. Aggressive Panhandling Bans. — Unlike location and blanket bans, appellate courts have not universally struck down bans on aggressive panhandling. While the Ninth Circuit has predictably 181 It is predictable because the same circuit had already ruled a more content-neutral law as content based in ACLU of Nev., 466 F.3d at 787–88; see also supra note 177 and accompanying text (discussing case). struck down such bans as content based, 182 See Berger v. City of Seattle, 569 F.3d 1029 (9th Cir. 2008) (en banc). In that case, an ordinance in Seattle allowed for street performances next to “captive audiences” waiting in line at Seattle Center, a public park frequented by tourists, but outlawed any “active solicitation” or direct requests for funds. See id. at 1036–37 (describing statute and Seattle Center). Thus, a person could perform a routine with a hat on the ground for donations but could not ask for people to put money in the hat. Id. The Ninth Circuit ruled the ordinance content based (and that it failed strict scrutiny), as enforcement would require inquiring into the message of the speech. Id. at 1052 (“How else would an officer determine whether a performer’s tip-of-the-cap was accompanied by a permissible ‘Thank you’ or a prohibited ‘Please give?’”). the Seventh Circuit has not. In Norton v. City of Springfield, the Seventh Circuit found a ban on panhandling in downtown Springfield, Illinois, content neutral and constitutional. 183 See supra notes 162–163 and accompanying text (describing Springfield statute at issue in Norton). The ban allowed silent panhandling but prevented active, verbal solicitations for immediate funds. 184 See Norton v. City of Springfield, 768 F.3d 713, 714 (7th Cir. 2014) (“The ordinance defines panhandling as an oral request for an immediate donation of money. Signs requesting money are allowed; so are oral pleas to send money later.”), rev’d, 806 F.3d 411 (7th Cir. 2015). The statute at issue in Norton also contained provisions prohibit­ing aggressive begging, such as using foul language or following pedestrians. See Eric Feldman, Springfield Panhandling Case Turned Away By SCOTUS, Fox Ill., (Feb. 29, 2016), http://foxillinois.com/news/local/springfield-panhandling-case-turned-away-by-scotus-03-01-2016 [http://perma.cc/8ZTW-BT3P] (discussing portions of law still in ef­fect after case was decided, including prohibition on panhandling people “standing in line and waiting,” “using profane or abusive language,” or “panhandling in a group or two or more persons”). Since these provisions did not apply to petitioner, they were not raised in any of the Norton decisions. See Norton, 806 F.3d at 412 (“Plaintiffs contend that the ordinance’s principal rule—barring oral requests for money now but not regulating requests for money later—is a form of content discrimination”).
The Eleventh Circuit treated a location ban as content neutral, but the holding is limited as, strangely, plaintiffs conceded the point. See Smith, 177 F.3d  at 956 (“Plaintiffs do not dispute that [the statute] is content-neutral . . . .”).
The ban had both elements of a location-based and aggressive-panhandling ban, albeit with a very low bar for what constituted aggressive. 185 See Berger, 569 F.3d at 1036–37 (describing statute); see also id. at 1057 (“[N]one of the rules differentiate between benign, inoffensive conduct and aggressive, unwelcome acts. They simply deter or ban all relevant speech.”). Similarly, in Thayer v. City of Worcester, Justice Souter—sitting by designation on the First Circuit—upheld Worcester’s aggressive-begging law after applying intermediate scrutiny. 186 755 F.3d 60, 78 (2014) (Souter, J.) (upholding Worcester panhandling regula­tion), vacated, 135 S. Ct. 2887 (2015). The regulation required authorities to inquire not only into whether the speech involved solicitation but also if the speech contained aggressive or violent language. 187 See id. at 65 (discussing Worcester statute). Justice Souter wrote that because the speech in question did not involve the government disagreeing with a particular message, it therefore was content neutral. 188 Id. at 67–68, 71.

The morass of appellate cases on panhandling shows that histori­cally, while a consensus existed that blanket bans and broad-based location bans were unconstitutional, there was disagreement concerning whether aggressive begging (often with elements of location bans) should be upheld. 189 See supra notes 169–172 and accompanying text (discussing appellate courts’ rejection of blanket bans similar to Loper). But as the next section will discuss, likely no regula­tion of panhandling is constitutional after Reed.

C. Reed v. Town of Gilbert Fundamentally Alters the Landscape

As the above section illustrated, appellate courts have struggled with where to draw the line between content neutral and content based speech regulations. This section describes how recent Supreme Court cases have changed the doctrinal landscape with the potential to bring uniformity to the law of panhandling regulation and content-neutral determinations as a whole.

The Supreme Court provided somewhat of an answer to what makes a law content neutral in the 2014 decision of McCullen v. Coakley. 190 134 S. Ct. 2518 (2014). While not explicitly overturning the previous abortion-protest case of Hill v. Colorado, 191 530 U.S. 703 (2000); see also supra notes 83–84 and accompanying text (discuss­ing Hill). the Court, in a 9-0 decision, struck down a Massachusetts law banning “knowingly standing” within thirty-five feet of a reproductive-health facility, with an exemption for clinic staff. 192 McCullen, 134 S. Ct. at 2522.

Chief Justice Roberts, as well as the liberal wing of the Court, found the law to be content neutral because it would not require authorities to “‘examine the content of the message that is conveyed to determine whether’ a violation has occurred,” since the law prohibited the conduct of those standing in the buffer zone regardless of their expression. 193 Id. at 2531 (quoting FCC v. League of Women Voters of Cal., 468 U.S. 364, 383 (1984)). Thus, to Chief Justice Roberts, because the statute in question only regulated the place and not the content of the message, it was content neutral. The Court did inquire into whether the Massachusetts legisla­ture had a content-based motive for enacting the legislation, but the Court ultimately accepted the legislature’s stated reasons of “public safety” and congestion as satisfying a content-neutral motive. 194 Id. at 2532 (concluding legislature acted “in response to a problem that was . . . limited” to areas statute sought to cover). This contrasted with the approach in several appellate courts of analyzing the governmental motive to determine if there was intent to discriminate based on content. 195 See, e.g., Thayer v. City of Worcester, 755 F.3d 60, 67 (1st Cir. 2014) (Souter, J.) (“In determining whether a particular regulation is content-neutral, the principal enquiry is ‘whether the government has adopted a regulation of speech because of disagreement with the message it conveys.’’’ (quoting Ward v. Rock Against Racism, 491 U.S. 781, 791 (1989))), vacated, 135 S. Ct. 2887 (2015); Clatterbuck v. City of Charlottesville, 708 F.3d 549, 555 (4th Cir. 2013) (“In this inquiry, ‘[t]he government’s purpose is the controlling consideration.’” (quoting Ward, 491 U.S. at 791)), abrogated by Cent. Radio Co. v. City of Norfolk, 811 F.3d 625 (4th Cir. 2016).

Justice Thomas went even further in Reed v. Town of Gilbert in discussing the content neutrality of a law that treated certain types of signs, such as political ones, more favorably than signs indicating the time and place of events—in this case sermons for a small local church. 196 135 S. Ct. 2218, 2225–26 (2015). Finding the law content based, Justice Thomas formulated a two-part test: Courts should inquire into governmental motive only after determining if it is “content neutral on its face.” 197 Id. at 2228.

Justice Thomas articulated the first step of the test—determining whether a law is “content neutral on its face”—in striking terms: “Government regulation of speech is content based if a law applies to particular speech because of the topic discussed or the idea or message expressed.” 198 Id. at 2227. Thus, Reed makes McCullen even more explicit: Any kind of parsing of the speech’s content merits strict scrutiny. 199 Id. (holding facial distinctions within regulation “drawn based on the message a speaker conveys” are “subject to strict scrutiny”). The sole inquiry needed in separating legal from illegal speech is whether the provision prohibits speech based on its substance. 200 Id. at 2228 (“A law that is content based on its face is subject to strict scrutiny regardless of the government’s benign motive, content-neutral justification, or lack of animus toward the ideas contained in the regulated speech.”(internal quotation marks omitted) (quoting City of Cincinnati v. Discovery Network, Inc., 507 U.S. 410, 429 (1993))). Of course, the content neutrality of the law is a necessary but not sufficient condition; a law could still fail the second part of the test due to the enacting government having a discriminatory intent. Id. 

It is debatable, however, whether Justice Thomas’s formulation of the content-neutrality test is a radical shift in doctrine or a regurgitation of existing doctrine. Three of the six Justices joining his opinion—Justices Kennedy, Alito, and Sotomayor—filed a separate concurring opinion noting that certain types of restrictions, such as one regulating signs for one-time events, differently than other signs, would be content neutral since they do not “discriminate based on topic or subject.” 201 Id. at 2233 (Alito, J., concurring). This seems to water down Justice Thomas’s belief that any parsing of content is unconstitutional; under his view, whether an event is a one-time event is a matter of message and content and would therefore be content based.

For Justice Kagan, however, the Thomas majority opinion marked a fundamental departure from existing precedent. In her concurrence in the judgment, she forcefully denounced the consequences of subjecting more laws to strict scrutiny under Justice Thomas’s formalist approach: “As the years go by, courts will discover that thousands of towns have such ordinances, many of them entirely reasona­ble. And as the challenges to them mount, courts will have to invalidate one after the other.” 202 Id. at 2239 (Kagan, J., concurring in the judgment) (citations omitted) (internal quotation marks omitted) (quoting id. at 2231 (majority opinion)).

Panhandling regulations can be classified into three distinct categories, which have often received different treatment among the appellate courts. This current state of affairs will likely change with the Supreme Court’s Reed decision: Under the new framework, all pan­handling regulations will likely be considered content based and therefore unconstitutional. Yet, as the next Part shows, interpreting Reed and its effects is no simple matter.

III. A New Paradigm

This Part describes how the vast majority of panhandling regulations are vulnerable to First Amendment challenges after Reed and offers a solution to the possibility that almost all panhandling regulation will be ruled unconstitutional. Section III.A demonstrates that nearly all existing panhandling laws are unconstitutional. Section III.B offers a possible solution that would enable courts to uphold meritorious panhandling laws: By invoking the fundamental rights invoked in the captive audience doctrine, courts could allow some regulations to pass strict scrutiny. Regardless of whether courts adopt this solution, this Part makes it clear that after Reed, the doctrinal status quo concerning panhandling laws is untenable.

A. Panhandling Laws Are Likely Unconstitutional

While the various opinions in Reed v. Gilbert might suggest that a majority of the Court is not ready to embrace Justice Thomas’s bright-line-rule formulation of content-based laws, 203 See supra section II.C (discussing Reed). the Court has already signaled that it envisions Reed overturning content-based laws. In Thayer v. City of Worcester, the Court remanded the decision to be considered in light of Reed, 204 Thayer v. City of Worcester, 135 S. Ct. 2887, 2887 (2015) (mem.). effectively overruling former-Justice Souter’s views that aggressive-begging statutes are content neutral. 205 See supra notes 186–188 and accompanying text (discussing Souter’s Thayer opinion). On remand, the district court predictably held that under Reed, Worcester’s statute was content based and failed strict scrutiny. 206 See Thayer v. City of Worcester, No. 13-40057-TSH, 2015 WL 6872450, at *12–13 (D. Mass. Nov. 9, 2015) (declaring aggressive-panhandling law was content based). The District Court Judge, Timothy Hillman, originally found the law to be content neutral when the case first entered the court system, see Thayer v. City of Worcester, 979 F. Supp. 2d 143, 154–55 (D. Mass. 2013). The District of Massachusetts has also struck down an aggressive-begging statute in Lowell, Massachusetts, with language indicating that the court views Reed as holding any panhandling regulation to be content based by its very nature:

[T]he Ordinance distinguishes solicitations for immediate donations from all others. A person could vocally request that passersby in the Historic District make a donation tomorrow, but not today (a distinction that may be of great import to someone seeking a meal and a bed tonight). He could ask passersby to sign a petition, but not a check. The City’s definition of panhandling targets a particular form of expressive speech—the solicitation of immediate charitable donations—[an]d applies its regulatory scheme only to that subject matter. 207 McLaughlin v. City of Lowell, No. 14-10270-DPW, 2015 WL 6453144, at *4 (D. Mass. Oct. 23, 2015).

Similarly, the Seventh Circuit has interpreted Reed as compelling the conclusion that aggressive-panhandling laws are content based. Judge Easterbrook, overturning his earlier Norton v. City of Springfield deci­sion, 208 768 F.3d 713 (7th Cir. 2014); see supra notes 183–188 and accompanying text (discussing Norton). defined the new legal landscape in stark terms: “Any law dis­tinguishing one kind of speech from another by reference to its meaning now requires a compelling justification,” 209 Norton v. City of Springfield, 806 F.3d 411, 412 (7th Cir. 2015). The ordinance in Norton had other bans on aggressive panhandling such as abusive language that seem even more content based and thus ripe for judicial challenge. See supra note 184 (discussing statute in greater detail). and the Supreme Court has denied a petition of certiorari from the City of Springfield. 210 City of Springfield v. Norton, 136 S. Ct. 1173 (2016) (mem.). The Fourth Circuit has also abrogated its current doctrine from Clatterbuck v. City of Charlottesville 211 708 F.3d 549 (4th Cir. 2013), abrogated by Cent. Radio Co. v. City of Norfolk, 811 F.3d 625 (4th Cir. 2016). In Clatterbuck the Fourth Circuit held a panhandling law to be content based, see supra note 173 and accompanying text, but had used the government’s purpose as a “controlling consideration.” Clatterbuck, 708 F.3d at 555; supra note 195 and accompanying text (discussing Clatterbuck and content neutrality). on content neutrality in panhandling laws. 212 Cent. Radio Co., 811 F.3d at 632 (abrogating Clatterbuck because Reed holds any distinction based on “‘idea or message expressed’” as content based (quoting Reed v. Town of Gilbert, 135 S Ct. 2218, 2227 (2015))). And the District of Colorado has held a panhandling law in Grand Junction to be content based in light of Reed. 213 Browne v. City of Grand Junction, No. 14-cv-00809-CMA-KLM, 2015 WL 5728755, at *7–11 (D. Colo. Sept. 30, 2015) (applying test in Reed to find panhandling regulation content based). The day after Browne, Denver suspended enforcement of its panhandling ordinance. See Training Bulletin, Denver Police Dep’t, Colorado District Court Strikes Down Grand Junction Aggressive Panhandling Ordinance 1 (Oct. 1, 2015), http://static.aclu-co.org/wp-content/uploads/2014/03/panhandling.DPD-Bulletin.10-1-15-2.pdf [http://perma.cc/CD9Z-65R8].

Aggressive-panhandling laws—originally envisioned as a way to regulate panhandling without threatening free speech 214 See supra notes 150–152 and accompanying text (discussing origins of aggressive-begging laws). —are poised to be the first casualty of Reed’s new formulation of content neutrality. Under any formulation of Justice Thomas’s opinion, it is nearly impossi­ble to imagine them surviving constitutional challenges.

As aggressive-panhandling laws target threatening language or persistent solicitations, they clearly regulate based on the message of the speech. It is a further step still to call blanket bans on panhandling and solicitation of immediate funds content neutral. Location and blanket bans ask only whether a beggar solicited money, not how he or she did so. Under Justice Kennedy’s concurrence in Lee, this act of requesting imme­di­ate funds is conduct as opposed to speech. 215 See Int’l Soc’y for Krishna Consciousness, Inc. v. Lee, 505 U.S. 672, 705 (1992) (expressing Justice Kennedy’s views that panhandling is conduct); see also supra note 142–144 (discussing Justice Kennedy’s views on panhandling and conduct). Under Justice Kennedy’s view then, blanket and location bans discriminate only on the basis of conduct.

Yet while asking for money does contain elements of conduct it also involves at least some speech. And this speech element is all that is needed under Reed. 216 See Reed v. Town of Gilbert, 135 S. Ct. 2218, 2227 (2015) (laying forth Justice Thomas’s new content-neutrality test); see also supra notes 196–201 (discussing new test). As the Sixth Circuit points out in Speet v. Schuette, blanket bans still require discerning between types of solicitation. 217 726 F.3d 867, 870 (6th Cir. 2013) (“Michigan’s anti-begging statute cannot withstand facial attack because it prohibits a substantial amount of solicitation, an activity that the First Amendment protects, but allows other solicitation based on content.”). For blanket bans, it would be impossible to know if a solicitation took place or was immediate without determining the content of the solicitation. An authority must inquire whether the panhandler simply said, “Good morning” or “Good morning, can you spare some change?” By examin­ing the content of the speech, this analysis fails Justice Thomas’s content-neutrality test. And unlike Justice Kennedy’s test in Lee, the justification or purpose for the panhandling ban would not save a facially content-based regulation after Reed. 218 See Reed, 135 S. Ct. at 2228 (noting government intent is entirely divorced from content-neutrality determinations).

Furthermore, even if a court viewed a blanket ban as content neutral, such regulation would still almost certainly fail intermediate scrutiny. 219 It is important to note that the court in Loper evaluated a blanket ban under intermediate scrutiny but still found it to be a constitutional violation. See supra note 110 and accompanying text (noting Loper court treated regulation as content neutral). Blanket bans afford no alternative means of communica­tion, 220 See supra notes 114–116 and accompanying text (noting Loper’s ruling concerning alternative means of communication). thus failing any time, place, or manner standard. 221 See supra notes 52–55 and accompanying text (discussing differences between O’Brien and time, place, and manner tests and noting some courts view alternative means of communication as requirement only for latter legal standard). Even if a court applied an OBrien test without an alternative means requirement, a court could not plausibly construe a broad regulation on all immediate solicita­tion as reasonably tailored or a closely drawn legislative solution to the problem of potential duress or threats. 222 See supra notes 47–48 and accompanying text (discussing intermediate scrutiny requirement for closely drawn statues). It is true that Justice Kennedy argued against this point in Lee, stating that seeking solicitations in the future serves as an alternative form of communication satisfying the time, place, and manner test. See Int’l Soc’y for Krishna Consciousness, Inc. v. Lee, 505 U.S. 672, 707–08 (1992) (Kennedy, J., concurring in the judgments) (“Requests for money continue to be permitted, and in the course of request­ing money solicitors may explain their cause, or the purposes of their organization, without violating the regulation. It is only if the solicitor accepts immediate payment that a violation occurs.”). While this might hold true for Hare Krishnas seeking donations, it does not hold muster for those panhandling: A beggar cannot secure future donations like an organized religion can. Finally, appellate courts have also universally adopted and embraced Loper and its condemnation of blanket bans on panhandling. See supra notes 121–128 and accompanying text (noting Loper’s wide adoption).

And in the incredibly unlikely event a blanket ban was both content neutral and narrowly tailored enough to pass intermediate scrutiny, an overbreadth challenge like that in Speet would likely succeed because the law would prevent First Amendment-protected solicitation in an attempt to prevent unprotected solicitation. 223 See Speet v. Schuette, 726 F.3d 867, 880 (6th Cir. 2013) (striking down statute using overbreadth doctrine). Thus, despite the colorable argu­ment that blanket bans are content neutral because one could conceive of them hinging only on what type of conduct is at issue, they lack the tailoring needed to pass the current consensus among appellate courts concerning tailoring of panhandling regulation.

Unlike blanket bans, location bans have a higher chance of passing intermediate scrutiny because they arguably allow for alternative methods of communication since they allow for panhandling in areas not covered by the location ban. But such a conclusion is not entirely convincing, as many location bans operate as de facto blanket bans that prohibit panhandling in the only areas of town worth begging in. 224 See supra note 165 and accompanying text (discussing critiques of location bans). A beggar lacking the ability to panhandle in areas with commercial or tourist traffic has no real meaningful alternative: There is good reason that beggars are not found among residential streets or industrial dis­tricts. The only location bans that would offer a meaningful alternative are those not focused on areas of commerce or foot traffic but those that protect very specific public areas where pedestrians are vulnerable. 225 The Fourth Circuit has recently considered a case where a Virginia county prevented panhandling on its roadways to protect pedestrian safety. See Reynolds v. Middleton, 779 F.3d 222, 224 (4th Cir. 2015) (describing ordinance at issue in case). Treating the regulation as content neutral, the court struck down the ordinance in part because the county did not attempt to ban panhandling only at busy intersections where there was evidence panhandling could or did create dangerous traffic situations. See id. at 231–32 (“That is, there is no evidence that the County ever tried to improve safety by prosecuting any roadway solicitors who actually obstructed traffic, or that it ever even considered prohibiting roadway solicitation only at those locations where it could not be done safely.”). Such a requirement of specific data would make such an ordinance far more difficult to enact and curtail its potential scope greatly. It is important to note that this case was decided several months before Reed and did not even address the likely possibility the ordinance would now be content based under Justice Thomas’s formulation of content neutrality. Thus like blanket bans, almost all location bans would fail intermediate scrutiny.

After Reed, panhandling regulations exist in a state of extreme vulnerability. Already, courts have held that under Reed, panhandling regulations discriminate on the basis of content. 226 See supra notes 204–213 and accompanying text (discussing Reed’s effects on panhandling laws). Aggressive-panhan­dling bans, which determine legality on the basis of how the speech is said, are especially vulnerable to being held content based. Location and blanket bans might have a better chance of being content neutral, but as they require examination of the expression in question, they are likely content based under Reed as well. And due to their lack of tailoring, intermediate scrutiny and overbreadth challenges also pose considerable danger to location and blanket bans. In the wake of Reed, panhandling regulation in America looks increasingly moribund. 227 That is not to say that municipalities have stopped trying to enact panhandling laws. See, e.g., Mid-Hudson News Network, Poughkeepsie to Crack Down on “Aggressive Panhandling,” Daily Freeman (Apr. 6, 2016, 6:53 am), http://www.dailyfreeman.com/ general-news/20160406/poughkeepsie-to-crack-down-on-aggressive-panhandling (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (discussing proposed Poughkeepsie, New York aggressive panhandling law). Furthermore, many panhandlers lack the means to challenge law or to vindicate their rights. See Rakin, supra note 153 (manuscript at 38) (noting poor have difficulty getting panhandling claims into court). But with more and more courts finding panhandling laws content based—evaporating panhandling laws—eventually cities will be deterred from enacting and enforcing panhandling regulation.

B. The Captive Audience Doctrine Is the Appropriate Framework for Evaluating Such Laws

This section proposes a possible solution to the problem of panhandling regulation in a post-Reed world. This section discusses whether municipalities need panhandling regulation at all. It then argues that cities can benefit from narrowly tailored regulation that protects captive audiences and proposes a framework for courts to balance the First Amendment rights of both speakers and listeners in the strict scrutiny context. Finally this section discusses how alternative doctrinal strategies to upholding panhandling laws do not sufficiently protect First Amendment interests.

A possible solution for cities after Reed is to accept their inability to legislate panhandling in public forums and to rely on other laws, such as harassment, to stop the worst actors who engage in repeated following or threats. 228 As an example, New York’s harassment laws make it illegal to follow a person in public with an intent to annoy or harass, see N.Y. Penal Law § 240.26 (McKinney 2008), or harasses them in a way to make them fear physical injury, id. § 240.25. While laws might successfully curb some negative behavior, requirements such as intent or fear of physical injury would leave much aggressive and potentially coercive solicitation as legal. 229 See id. §§ 240.25–.26.

It is also important to note that while panhandling has positive effects on a free society, 230 See supra notes 117–120 (discussing beneficial aspects of panhandling). it also has several downsides. Panhandlers can pressure people into giving money against their will 231 See Roger Conner, Aggressive Panhandling Laws: Do These Statutes Violate the Constitution?, No: A Solution to Intimidation, A.B.A. J., June 1993, at 40–41 (arguing many, especially women and elderly, feel “they have narrowly escaped being mugged, assaulted, and robbed” after giving money to panhandlers). or in some instances commit outright fraud. 232 See, e.g., Joseph Goldstein & Jeffrey E. Singer, If He Walks and Talks Like a Monk, but Has His Hand Out, N.Y. Times (July 5, 2014), http://www.nytimes.com/ 2014/07/06/nyregion/panhandlers-dressed-as-monks-confound-new-yorkers.html (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (discussing panhandlers in Times Square impersonating Buddhist monks in effort to receive money). Perhaps even more troubling is that beggars and panhandlers, some of whom suffer from mental disorders or alcohol and drug addictions, can prove dangerous to individuals’ safety. 233 See Teir, supra note 150, at 290 & nn.14–15 (describing instances in which panhandlers posed significant safety risks). Finally, the pestering nature of some panhandlers can make citi­zens “callous” to the plight of the homeless and perhaps less likely to give to institutional charities or support political positions that protect the needy. 234 See Millich, supra note 117, at 257, 266–69 (describing problem known as “compassion fatigue” where panhandling makes listeners of the speech less receptive to helping poor).

Therefore, within the realm of constitutional reason, it seems that municipalities should have some leeway to regulate some panhandling. While Justice Thomas’s bright-line rule in Reed does not differentiate among panhandling laws, 235 See section II.C (discussing Reed). the laws themselves have very different impacts on speech: Blanket bans and location bans unjustly chill all panhandlers including those passively asking for change, while aggressive bans that are sufficiently targeted against bad actors, seem a reasonable method for cities to protect their streets when audiences are captive. Yet, such aggressive-panhandling laws are by their very definition contingent on the speech’s message and therefore content based. 236 See supra section II.B.2.a (discussing aggressive-begging laws). This Note proposes the solution that while aggressive-begging laws might be content based and subject to strict scrutiny, that does not mean they are necessarily unconstitutional. 237 See supra notes 35–38 and accompanying text (discussing how laws discriminat­ing on subject matter rarely, but sometimes do, pass strict scrutiny test). It is also possible, as Justice Breyer noted in his opinion in Reed—concurring in the judgment and joining Justice Kagan’s opinion—that Reed’s new test will force courts to water down the strict scrutiny test because so many regulations will now be content based. Reed v. Town of Gilbert, 135 S. Ct. 2218, 2235 (2015) (Breyer, J., concurring in the judgment) (“[T]he Court could escape the problem by watering down the force of the presumption against constitutionality that ‘strict scrutiny’ normally carries with it. But, in my view, doing so will weaken the First Amendment’s protection in instances where ‘strict scrutiny’ should apply in full force.”). As there is not yet evidence of dilution of the strict scrutiny test, this Note will work under the assumption that Reed will not alter the strict scrutiny test’s meaning.

The Court has shown a willingness to uphold laws on strict scrutiny when the regulation in question protects important rights. 238 See Case Comment, McCullen, supra note 39, at 228 (noting argument for passing strict scrutiny “is particularly strong when the restriction on speech serves to advance another constitutional interest”). For exam­ple, in Burson v. Freeman, a regulation on political speech around polling places passed strict scrutiny due to the importance of the fundamental right of voting in an election free of intimidation and fraud. 239 504 U.S. 191, 211 (1992). A recent Harvard Law Review comment argued for a balancing of abortion rights with those of speech rights for abortion-protest cases. See Case Comment, McCullen, supra note 39, at 229 (arguing for upholding of some laws under strict scrutiny in order to “advance another constitutional interest”).

Panhandling challenges should be seen as a struggle between two First Amendment rights: the right of beggars to express themselves and bystanders to remove themselves from uncomfortable speech. 240 See supra section I.C (discussing captive audience doctrine). This approach, while never broadly advocated for, does have some support from Judge Alex Kozinski of the Ninth Circuit. In his dissent in Berger, Judge Kozinski argued that “[c]itizens visiting the Center also have First Amendment rights: to enjoy the arts, music and programs offered there.” 241 Berger v. City of Seattle, 569 F.3d 1029, 1062 (9th Cir. 2009) (en banc) (Kozinski, J., dissenting); see also supra note 182 (discussing Berger). This captive audience approach would also yield results more in line with what one would expect and desire doctrine to produce within the categorical framework of panhandling laws:

  • Aggressive-begging statutes that targeted panhandlers who make their audiences captive would possess a chance of passing strict scrutiny.
  • Extremely specific location bans in places like subway cars 242 See supra notes 98–99 and accompanying text (discussing ordinance in Young). or lines for popular attractions where audiences cannot avoid panhandling would also stand a chance at surviving such a balancing test regardless of whether or not those venues were public or nonpublic forums. More general location bans, such as those in a popular area of town, would fail because it would ensnare panhandlers who did not create a captive environment.
  • Blanket bans, which would prevent panhandling that did not create a captive audience, would fail constitutional challenges.

This Note is under no Pollyannaish notion that it is extremely probable courts would adopt the captive audience doctrine to rule panhandling laws constitutional. McCullen v. Coakley seemingly has scaled back the importance of captive audience rights. McCullen, however, pertained to a wide-open sidewalk where people could walk away after a short amount of time. Aggressive panhandling situations could certainly involve a more “captive audience.” Furthermore, the issue in McCullen was whether the protesters had the right to protest in front of the clinic at all—not whether they were prohibited from certain abusive language or scare tactics. 243 See McCullen v. Coakley, 134 S. Ct. 2518, 2525 (2014) (discussing Massachusetts statute banning standing and therefore protesting in front of abortion clinics). And using the captive audience doctrine is more attrac­tive when considering the alternative methods to saving panhandling regulations.

For example, some may propose that an approach to preserve regulations after Reed would be the so-called secondary-effects doctrine, 244 See William L. Mitchell II, Comment, “Secondary Effects” Analysis: A Balanced Approach to the Problem of Prohibitions on Aggressive Panhandling, 24 U. Balt. L. Rev. 291, 322–26 (1994) (arguing for using secondary-effects doctrine to justify panhandling regulation). which allows for a court to treat a regulation as content neutral if it is aimed at the secondary effects of the speech, such as increasing crime rates or other threats to public safety. 245 See David L. Hudson, Jr., The Secondary-Effects Doctrine: Stripping Away First Amendment Freedoms, 23 Stan. L. & Pol’y Rev. 19, 19–20 (2012) (defining doctrine). This doctrine has its roots—and is almost exclusively applied—in the context of strip clubs and other adult-entertainment venues. 246 See, e.g., City of Renton v. Playtime Theatres, Inc., 475 U.S. 41, 47–48 (applying secondary-effects doctrine to regulation of adult cinema); Mark Rienzi & Stuart Buck, Neutral No More: Secondary Effects Analysis and the Quiet Demise of the Content-Neutrality Test, 82 Fordham L. Rev. 1187, 1189 (“Modern commentary suggests most scholars agree that the secondary effects doctrine has been largely cabined to sexually explicit speech.”). But see id. at 1210–11 (arguing secondary-effects doctrine has seeped into (pre-Reed) content-neutrality determinations). In addition to the fact that it is unlikely the court will explicitly expand the secondary-effects doctrine beyond the purview of sexual speech, panhandling laws directly target the act and conduct of panhandling and the direct risk that the speech will involve possible fraud or duress, not incidental crimes that panhandling would encourage. Furthermore, it seems impossible to prove that panhandling is the cause of increased crime in an area. A large number of tourists or poor people are in conditions where both panhandling and other crimes thrive, but that does not mean that panhandling is the cause of those crimes. Finally, after Reed it is still an open question if the secondary-effects doctrine remains relevant in determining content-based speech regulations.

Another likely avenue cities may look to in order to continue regu­lating panhandling after Reed is that of the nonpublic forum. 247 For a definition of nonpublic forums, see supra notes 62–65 and accompanying text. Unlike regulations for public forums, laws modifying nonpublic forums only need to avoid viewpoint discrimination and be reasonable. 248 See supra notes 66–68 and accompanying text (discussing scrutiny for nonpublic forums). New York City’s ban on begging on the subways is therefore likely constitu­tional, even after Reed. 249 This would also extend to the Port Authority’s bans in the World Trade Center and the Port Authority Bus Terminal. See supra note 13 (discussing bans in New York City subway and other locations). Cities may begin to adopt a strategy of using nonpublic forums, or carefully constructed designated public fo­rums, 250 For a definition of designated public forums, see supra notes 58–61 and accompanying text. to enforce at least some of their previously unconstitutional bans. Indeed, New York  City is considering assigning large portions of Times Square as either “civic zones” or “flow zones” where panhandling is not allowed, while assigning other parts of the square as “activity zones.” 251 See A Roadmap for a 21st Century Times Square, A Better Times Square, http://www.abettertimessquare.org/the-plan/ [http://perma.cc/7V58-WR6L] (last vis­ited Apr. 4, 2016) (outlining plan to reduce panhandling in Times Square); see also Jonathan Lemire, Times Square’s Topless Women Discussed at Task Force Meeting, Associated Press (Sept. 17, 2015, 6:56 pm), http://bigstory.ap.org/article/9eb3628be9a04a07a81cad98fb 738783/task-force-meets-address-time-squares-topless-women [http://perma.cc/ 6B6S-3B8Q]. As of the writing of this Note, the proposal had passed through the New York City Council, setting up a likely legal challenge in the future. See Emma G. Fitzsimmons, New York Moves on Restricting Costumed Characters in Times Square, N.Y. Times (Apr. 7, 2016), http://www.nytimes.com/2016/04/08/nyregion/new-york-council-votes-to-allow-restrictions-on-times-square-performers.html (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (noting City Council had allowed New York’s Department of Transportation to enact new zones for Times Square and quoting one Spiderman performer as saying he would sue if he were arrested under new laws). But using nonpublic forums as a way to curb unwanted panhandling is far from an ideal solution. Not only is it difficult for a city to say that much of its public space is not a public forum, but if a city could carry out the difficult task of deeming much of its space nonpublic forums, it would have further latitude to create panhandling and other speech laws. If this were to come to pass, Reed would have the unintended conse­quences of removing public space and creating more speech regulation as cities are forced to resort to other means to pass laws on panhandling.

Unlike the secondary-effects doctrine or using nonpublic forums, the captive audience doctrine allows for transparency and honesty among the courts concerning First Amendment rights. Using such an approach will allow for normative choices about what First Amendment rights are important in our society as opposed to a bright-line rule that invalidates virtually all panhandling regulation and ignores the fact that both listeners and speakers have constitutional rights.

Conclusion

Panhandling, while never explicitly recognized as protected speech by the Supreme Court, has steadily gained acceptance throughout appellate courts as speech covered under the First Amendment. 252 See supra section I.A (discussing panhandling as constitutionally protected speech). The circuit courts did not agree, however, on how exactly to define those protections or whether to treat panhandling regulations as content based or content neutral. Justice Thomas’s new two-step test in Reed v. Town of Gilbert seems to answer many of those questions, creating a definition for content-based laws that will likely result in many panhandling regulations being ruled content based and therefore struck down under the exacting requirements of strict scrutiny. 253 135 S. Ct. 2218, 2227–28 (2015) (formulating two-part test for determining if laws discriminate based on content); see also supra section II.C (discussing Reed). Already, several panhandling regula­tions have been ruled as content based and unconstitutional under the Reed framework. 254 See supra notes 204–213 and accompanying text (discussing Reed’s effects on panhandling laws).

In her Reed v. Town of Gilbert concurrence, Justice Kagan expressed concern about the invalidation of entirely reasonable laws under Justice Thomas’s new two-step test to determine content neutrality. 255 Reed, 135 S. Ct. at 2239 (Kagan, J., concurring in the judgment) (arguing Reed would have deleterious effects on First Amendment doctrine by invalidating too many laws as content based); see also supra note 202 and accompanying text (discussing Justice Kagan’s concurrence in the judgment).  While certain panhandling laws are unreasonable restrictions on free speech, carefully tailored location and aggressive-panhandling bans that protect those who are captive to panhandlers seem to be the exact type of laws Justice Kagan was worried about. The solution to Reed’s shift in the doctrinal landscape is to analyze begging laws under strict scrutiny but also to balance the rights of those speaking with the fundamental First Amendment rights of their captive audiences. By doing this, courts can honor the listener’s right not to have to endure harassing speech, value and protect the speaker’s First Amendment rights, and allow for the streets of America’s cities to be both pleasant thoroughfares and mean­ingful forums for expression.