I will never forget the day my mother found out she was the source of my HLA-B27 positivity and told me: “I am sorry.” It was several years after my diagnosis with a chronic illness that has and would cause me suffering. My mother was made to feel that by having a disabled child, she did something wrong. This Note is about the systems that instilled in my mother the need to say sorry.
It is better for all the world, if instead of waiting to execute degenerate offspring for crime, or to let them starve for their imbecility, society can prevent those who are manifestly unfit from continuing their kind.
– Oliver Wendell Holmes, Buck v. Bell.
Introduction
Developments in reproductive technology are introducing new possibilities for reproductive health, genetic testing, and disease eradication. Simultaneously, legislators and the judiciary have decreased autonomy in reproductive choices. This pernicious combination presents challenges for many women
seeking reproductive care and protection from federal antidiscrimination laws when healthcare providers make decisions based on unsubstantiated and even intolerant preconceptions about the quality of disabled life.
Parallel to other civil rights statutes, the Americans with Disabilities Act (ADA) covers people, and primarily people with disabilities. Under Title III of the ADA, “[n]o individual shall be discriminated against on the basis of disability in the full and equal enjoyment of the goods, services, facilities, privileges, advantages, or accommodations of any place of public accommodation.”
The 2008 Amendments (ADAAA) clarified that disability definitions should be construed broadly, favoring coverage to the maximum extent possible under the terms of the ADA.
Yet the ADA has not been interpreted to afford broad coverage to those with unexpressed genetic indicators for disability.
The ADA and its Amendments provide little recourse, then, for women with genetic indicators for disease who are denied assisted reproductive technology (ART) services on that basis.
Fertility clinics have the discretion to refuse these women equal access to healthcare services based on disability-related animus, and the law provides no remedy. In fact, the United States’ weak regulatory framework on ART
and the American Society for Reproductive Medicine’s (ASRM) recommendation that physicians consider “the well-being of offspring” in determining whether to deny services
encourages such preconceptions to drive reproductive healthcare. At present, antidiscrimination law affords few protections for individuals with genetic conditions,
just as technology renders genetic conditions easier to detect and weed out.
Published studies and reporting mechanisms documenting fertility clinic practitioner refusals to transfer embryos are lacking.
Nonetheless, fertility clinic policies and patient anecdotes confirm the regularity of the practice.
Popular media has amplified anecdotes of disabled people seeking in-vitro fertilization (IVF) to intentionally select for disabled embryos, such as a deaf lesbian couple seeking a deaf sperm donor.
In general, fertility clinic physicians have refused these types of requests, with one Maryland-based physician telling the New York Times, “In general, one of the prime dictates of parenting is to make a better world for our children . . . . Dwarfism and deafness are not the norm.”
In one infamous case, a deaf lesbian couple from Maryland employed sperm from a deaf male friend because they sought a deaf baby,
and conservative commentators decried the act as creating “victims from birth.”
Some couples, on the other hand, use genetic testing to determine whether their embryos carry genes for certain impairments—even with the initial aim of selecting against disability
—but seek implantation of some genetically anomalous embryos notwithstanding the test’s results. Selecting for traits raises numerous ethical questions;
at present, the arbiters of these ethical debates are clinics
rather than the individuals producing these embryos. Policies prohibiting implantation of genetically anomalous embryos not only screen out prospective parents seeking disabled children but also refuse service to those for whom selection of viable genetically anomalous embryos represents their only opportunity at biological parenthood.
Women predisposed to having disabled children face compounded constraints on reproductive autonomy. A woman who is an asymptomatic genetic carrier for Duchenne Muscular Dystrophy (DMD) can be denied services by a fertility clinic because any son she conceives has a fifty percent chance of developing DMD.
A mother to two deaf sons can be denied reproductive care after her embryos test positive for a gene associated with hearing impairment.
An aspiring mother who can only afford one round of IVF can be denied the implantation of any of her embryos because they carry a genetic indicator for autoimmune diseases.
While federal law prohibits genetic discrimination in employment and health insurance,
and disallows service denials based on disability,
fertility clinics’ refusals to provide reproductive services on the basis of genetic conditions go largely unchecked. In many cases, women are not presently disabled enough to qualify for the ADA’s protections, but nevertheless become victims of discrimination in reproductive services based on stereotypes about disabled people. Permitting this gap in antidiscrimination law to persist legitimizes the devaluation of disabled lives, prevents some women with genetic conditions from becoming mothers, and kindles the fire igniting current debates surrounding fetal personhood legislation.
This Note highlights the risks of allowing unchecked fertility clinic discretion in assisted reproductive technology to persist and proposes several possible solutions that bridge antidiscrimination principles and women’s autonomy.