MONOPOLIZING BY CONDITIONING

MONOPOLIZING BY CONDITIONING

Across the economy, monopolists of all kinds are engaged in “conditional dealing.” This is the practice of unilaterally offering benefits and penalties, or bribes and threats, to induce trading partners to refrain from competing against the monopolist or from dealing with its rivals. Pharma giants offer discounts conditioned on “loyalty,” agricultural monopolists impose “exit penalties” for switching to rivals, and social networks offer interoperability for apps only so long as they don’t compete.

Economic scholarship shows that conditional dealing can inflict serious harms, but the law has not caught up. In particular, harmful conditioning goes undeterred because it falls into the gaps between the categories of our fragmented monopolization law. Courts have repeatedly tried to squeeze conditioning into ill-fitting categories, rejected claims on the basis of economically irrelevant criteria, and sometimes thrown up their hands altogether. The result: shambolic doctrine, tolerance of harmful behavior, and the collapse of enforcement efforts.

Conditional dealing should be recognized as a new category of monopolizing conduct. To that end, this Article provides a new analytical framework: a definition of conditioning, as well as standards for gauging its exclusionary impact, contribution to power, and procompetitive justifications. It explains why a host of criteria often applied by courts—from price-cost and “coercion” tests to quantitative foreclosure screens—should be jettisoned. And it sketches two further ideas with broader implications for antitrust: a framework of “quick look monopolization” for nakedly harmful conditioning and a reinterpretation of the “attempted monopoly maintenance” offense to tackle knowing misconduct in complex markets.

The full text of this Article can be found by clicking the PDF link to the left.

Introduction

What could be more flagrantly anticompetitive than bribing or threatening a business to deter it from becoming, or from dealing with, a competitor? Surely, one might think, any self-respecting antitrust system would come down very hard on a monopolist that tried anything of the kind.

But the practice is rife. Enforcers have sued digital platforms for offering an array of valuable benefits—from search preferencing to interoperability—to encourage their trading partners to steer clear of rivals and rivalry. 1 See infra section I.A.1. “Search preferencing” means more favorable treatment in search results (e.g., higher ranking, or display in a featured box or sidebar); “interoperability” means interconnection between compatible products and services. These have featured in allegations against Amazon and Meta (Facebook) respectively. See infra notes 28–33, 58–61 and accompanying text. Agritech giants pay distributors to reject cheaper crop protection chemicals that would reduce farmers’ costs. 2 See infra section I.A.2 (discussing an FTC suit alleging anticompetitive “loyalty discounting” by two agritech companies). And pharmaceutical monopolists wield enormous rebates to induce customers to refuse cheaper generic alternatives that patients would value. 3 See infra section I.A.3 (describing how pharmaceutical companies use rebates to keep certain drugs off approved formularies).

And when enforcers do challenge such practices—typically under the prohibition on “monopolization” in Section 2 of the Sherman Act 4 See Sherman Act of 1890, 15 U.S.C. § 2 (2018) (“Every person who shall monopolize, or attempt to monopolize . . . any part of the trade or commerce among the several States . . . shall be deemed guilty of a felony . . . .”). —courts often seem barely interested. For example, the D.C. Circuit has effectively shrugged at an allegation that a dominant social network leveraged valuable interoperability to deter other apps from developing competing functions, 5 See New York v. Meta Platforms, Inc., 66 F.4th 288, 305–06 (D.C. Cir. 2023) (applying refusal to deal law and rejecting plaintiff’s theory of harm). while the Ninth Circuit showed little interest in allegations that a processor-chip monopolist used a patent license as a vehicle to surcharge customers’ dealings with rivals. 6 See Fed. Trade Comm’n v. Qualcomm Inc., 969 F.3d 974, 997–1003 (9th Cir. 2020) (holding that the FTC’s “‘anticompetitive surcharge’ theory fails to state a cogent theory of anticompetitive harm”). So what’s going on? What’s the point, one might ask, of having a monopolization statute if it doesn’t catch this kind of thing?

It turns out that antitrust does a staggeringly bad job at handling practices of this kind. These are all examples of conditional dealing: a monopolist treating other market participants more favorably when they refrain from (or limit) competition against the monopolist, or refrain from (or limit) dealing with its rivals. In a paradigmatic conditional dealing case, there is no actual agreement or commitment that the counterparty won’t compete or won’t deal with rivals. Instead, there is just an explicit or implied policy, unilaterally applied by the monopolist, that punishes competition and rewards “loyalty.” The inducement may be naked (e.g., cash payments or penalties) or it may involve differentiated terms of trade with the monopolist (e.g., granting or withholding access to a product or service, or offering better or worse prices, to encourage “loyalty”).

Conditional dealing falls into a troubling gap in antitrust doctrine. On the one hand, antitrust has fairly clear rules for agreements involving monopolists, including deals with rivals to avoid competition (“market allocation” agreements), 7 See Palmer v. BRG of Georgia, Inc., 498 U.S. 46, 49–50 (1990) (describing a market allocation agreement as “unlawful on its face”). and deals requiring trading partners to cut off rivals (“exclusivity” agreements). 8 See Tampa Elec. Co. v. Nashville Coal Co., 365 U.S. 320, 327 (1961) (holding that a substantial foreclosure standard applied to the analysis of an exclusive agreement). These rules provide for fairly close scrutiny. Agreements of the first kind are usually per se illegal; 9 See, e.g., Palmer, 498 U.S. at 49–50. agreements of the second kind are analyzed to determine whether rivals are being harmfully and unjustifiably foreclosed. 10 See, e.g., Tampa Elec., 365 U.S. at 327.

On the other hand, antitrust also has fairly clear rules for unilateral choices about pricing and supply. These rules, by contrast, are highly permissive, amounting to virtual immunity. Thus, above-cost pricing is usually per se legal, even if customers complain that a monopolist’s prices are too high or competitors complain they are too low. 11 See Pac. Bell Tel. Co. v. Linkline Commc’ns, Inc., 555 U.S. 438, 449–53 (2009) (rejecting a “price-squeeze” theory of antitrust liability); Brooke Grp. Ltd. v. Brown & Williamson Tobacco Corp., 509 U.S. 209, 222–23 (1993) (holding that liability for predatory pricing claims requires a showing of below-cost pricing). And businesses can generally refuse to deal with their rivals at will. 12 See, e.g., Verizon Commc’ns Inc. v. Law Offs. of Curtis V. Trinko, LLP, 540 U.S. 398, 408 (2004) (“[A]s a general matter, the Sherman Act ‘does not restrict the long recognized right of [a] trader or manufacturer engaged in an entirely private business, freely to exercise his own independent discretion as to parties with whom he will deal.’” (second alteration in original) (quoting United States v. Colgate & Co., 250 U.S. 300, 307 (1919))). In theory, it’s possible for a refusal to deal to violate the antitrust laws, 13 See, e.g., Aspen Skiing Co. v. Aspen Highlands Skiing Corp., 472 U.S. 585, 601–11 (1985) (imposing liability for the termination of a cooperative venture with a smaller rival). but the eye of that needle is so slender that no plaintiff has squeezed through it in decades. 14 See Erik Hovenkamp, The Antitrust Duty to Deal in the Age of Big Tech, 131 Yale L.J. 1483, 1490 n.26 (2022) [hereinafter Hovenkamp, Big Tech] (noting that no plaintiff has won a refusal case since 2004).

Conditional dealing falls right between these two categories. It seems to present all the dangers of classically harmful agreements, regardless of whether an actual agreement exists, and regardless of how the threats and bribes are labeled, paid, or extracted. But it also seems to implicate all the liberty concerns that attend unilateral pricing and supply choices. After all, if there is no general antitrust duty to deal with the world, it seems to follow that a monopolist can choose to sell only to noncompetitors, or to sell to them on more favorable terms. That position even has some everyday intuitive appeal: Why should a business have to sell to its own rivals, or to businesses that choose to partner with its rivals?

Conditioning ruthlessly exposes a deep problem with the monopolization offense: its discomfort with practices that do not fall into its clean, shoebox-like categories (like exclusivity or tying) and that force courts to rely on monopolization’s elusive and uncertain first principles. 15 See, e.g., Thomas A. Lambert, Defining Unreasonably Exclusionary Conduct: The “Exclusion of a Competitive Rival” Approach, 92 N.C. L. Rev. 1175, 1177 (2014) (noting that the “problem with Section 2” is that “nobody knows what it means”); see also Daniel Francis, Making Sense of Monopolization, 84 Antitrust L.J. 779, 784 (2022) [hereinafter Francis, Making Sense of Monopolization] (“[T]he core idea of ‘monopolization’ remains maddeningly elusive.”). It’s all very well to say, as courts often do, that monopolization law asks whether conduct is “anticompetitive” or “predatory” rather than “competition on the merits,” but that kind of sloganeering is virtually no help in the real world. 16 See Daniel Francis, Antitrust Without Competition, 74 Duke L.J. 353, 358 (2024), [hereinafter Francis, Competition] (criticizing the use of an “unliquidated competition criterion”); Herbert Hovenkamp, The Slogans and Goals of Antitrust Law, 25 N.Y.U. Legis. & Pub. Pol’y 705, 745–51 (2023) (“[A]n antitrust concern articulated as a ‘protection of the competitive process’ does not give us much help unless we have some background substance to tell us what intelligent competition policy is.”).

So courts—and some commentators—tend to try to jam conditioning into an existing shoebox, often one that is subject to heavily pro-defendant rules. For example, when a coalition of states alleged that the Facebook personal social network dangled valuable interoperability to deter app developers from developing competing functions, the D.C. Circuit analyzed that practice as a simple refusal to deal: a practice that, as noted above, is virtually per se legal. 17 See New York v. Meta Platforms, Inc., 66 F.4th 288, 305–06 (D.C. Cir. 2023). And when the FTC alleged that Qualcomm, a leading chip supplier, used patent licenses as a vehicle to tax customers’ dealings with its rivals, the Ninth Circuit analyzed the claim as a complaint primarily about excessive royalty rates, and automatic legality followed. 18 See Fed. Trade Comm’n v. Qualcomm Inc., 969 F.3d 974, 1000–03 (9th Cir. 2020). In still other cases, courts have been persuaded to apply an array of tests—“coercion,” below-cost pricing, the “predominance” of price, duration and terminability, and so on 19 See infra section II.A. —that have little or nothing to do with the underlying dangers, notwithstanding the rich economic literature protesting that these considerations are beside the point.

This economic literature leaves no doubt that conditioning can enable a monopolist to do just what the Sherman Act abhors: inflict welfare harms by excluding rivals in ways that contribute to monopoly power and are not justified by offsetting benefits. 20 See infra section I.B. But antitrust’s ability to respond to harmful conditioning is being hobbled by the structure of monopolization doctrine: specifically, its heavy reliance on analytical categories that were designed to respond to other, rather different, practices. 21 See infra section II.A. In other words, this is a problem that the law has created for itself. Economists seem perfectly clear-eyed about the effects and dangers of conditional dealing. 22 See infra section I.B.

Monopolization’s failure to reckon with conditioning is holding back efforts to deal with some of the most pressing concerns on the antitrust agenda. This includes, for example, concerns about platform monopolists proffering a benefit (like interoperability or better search rankings) to induce their trading partners to disfavor rivals; 23 See infra section I.A.1. agricultural monopolists using conditional discounts and “exit penalties” to prevent rivals from getting a foothold; 24 See infra section I.A.2. and pharmaceutical monopolists using rebates to keep lower-cost competitors down or out in markets for life-saving treatment. 25 See infra section I.A.3. In these and other areas, monopoly conditioning may threaten worse harms than just higher prices.

*    *    *

This Article argues that we should meet conditional dealing on its own terms by recognizing a new category of monopolizing conduct. Anticompetitive conditioning or conditional dealing is the application by a monopolist of conditions that punish others for competing with it (horizontal conditioning) or for trading with its rivals (vertical conditioning).

This Article unfolds in three parts. Part I presents the problem: conditional dealing by monopolists. It surveys the uses and dangers of this practice in a selection of critical tech, agriculture, and healthcare markets, then synthesizes the rich body of economic scholarship on conditioning and its effects.

Part II sets out the Article’s primary contribution: a new analytical framework for courts and others analyzing conditioning under Section 2 of the Sherman Act. This includes a test for identifying conditional dealing (the “hold-constant” test) and a doctrinal framework for assessing its legality. This involves assessments of whether a condition has an exclusionary incidence on rivals (i.e., whether a horizontal condition significantly impairs the incentives of one or more rivals to meet demand, or whether a vertical condition significantly impairs the ability of one or more rivals to do so by substantially foreclosing their access to inputs, distribution, customers, or complements); whether the exclusion is reasonably capable of contributing significantly to monopoly power; and whether the practice is justified by offsetting welfare benefits.

This Part also explains why many factors often emphasized by courts and others—from price-cost measures and coercion tests to doctrines of de facto exclusivity—should have no place in this analysis. And, using conditional dealing as a vehicle to explore some broader questions of principle, this Part proposes some more general course corrections for antitrust: a modest regrounding of the concept of substantial foreclosure; a clarification that free riding in an antitrust case is, without more, a neutral fact, not a trump card for a defendant; and the long-overdue recognition that an unconditional refusal to deal is per se lawful, notwithstanding the agonizing refusal of courts to say this out loud. Part II also points out some landmarks in antitrust’s precedential canon that are best understood as conditioning cases.

Part III sketches two further ideas to reinforce monopolization’s frontier. The first idea is what might be called quick look monopolization. It draws on a doctrine developed under Section 1 of the Sherman Act that, in clear cases, a plaintiff may establish a prima facie case by reference to the basic nature and context of the agreement without having to piece together evidence of actual effects or impacts. 26 See Cal. Dental Ass’n v. Fed. Trade Comm’n, 526 U.S. 756, 770 (1999) (noting that certain agreements may be found anticompetitive without elaborate analysis of the market so long as the “great likelihood of anticompetitive effects can easily be ascertained”). This approach has never been applied in monopolization law, but it should be, because its logic applies equally in that setting. It provides a principled way to sharpen monopolization doctrine in a small subset of clear cases, including conditioning cases lacking plausible justifications.

The second idea is a reinterpretation of the offense of attempted monopoly maintenance. Conventional accounts present the attempt offense as a sort of mini-monopolization: that is, a ban on conduct by a near-monopolist that has provably resulted in actual exclusion and actual contribution to power. But the offense also bears a second, neglected reading: a prohibition of conduct by an actual monopolist that is intended to cause welfare harms by suppressing rival ability and incentive to compete and which is dangerously likely to have led to that outcome—regardless of whether it really did have that effect. It provides a principled way to deter intentional misconduct, even in our most complex and dynamic markets.

Ultimately, this Article’s central claim is a simple and intuitive one. A monopolist’s use of an explicit or implicit condition to punish trading partners for competing, or for dealing with competitors, is a distinct form of antitrust wrongdoing, not an edge-case example of a more familiar practice like tying or predatory pricing. Just like other familiar kinds of violations, conditioning presents clear, well-understood risks of consumer harm, and it can be scrutinized by courts without unreasonable intrusion on the freedom of businesses to run their affairs. When a monopolist uses such a practice to exclude rivals and augment its monopoly, courts should demand evidence of justification—and should impose liability if it is not forthcoming. Such claims should not be shrugged off for failure to fit neatly into a handful of doctrinal boxes that were crafted with very different practices in mind.

It is time to close antitrust’s conditioning loophole.