Introduction
We are living in a moment of reckoning for U.S. criminal policy. In recent years, as police brutality has gone viral and the drug war has been exposed as ineffective and racist, many progressive politicians,
academics,
organizations,
organizers,
and voters
have aligned themselves with moves toward decarceration or police and prison abolition. Increasingly, many progressive commentators criticize mass incarceration and treat criminal legal institutions as objectionable responses to social problems.
Nevertheless, these anticarceral commitments often have their limits. Despite the prevalence of increasingly radical rhetoric on the left, many progressives continue to make exceptions and favor criminal solutions when presented with particularly sympathetic victims or particularly unsympathetic defendants.
In this Essay, we aim to describe and explain why many on the political left (broadly conceived) who generally favor decarceration selectively turn to the carceral state to solve social problems.
This kind of selective reliance on the carceral system is widespread in today’s progressive movements,
and it has not been addressed adequately by the current scholarly literature. We believe that confronting this reliance on criminal law is essential to any movement that aims to take widespread decarceration or abolition of the carceral state seriously. Critics must grapple with what social movements and commentators on the left continue to find promising about criminal law.
Our claim is that critical accounts tend to miss the possible explanatory power of distribution (or redistribution) as a way of understanding why otherwise-decarceral progressive activists might favor criminalization in certain situations.
Viewed in this light, criminal legal institutions might be justified as vehicles for redistributing power and resources to marginalized victims and away from defendants based on wealth, race, gender, sexuality, or other privileged societal positions.
A redistributive justification for criminalization or punishment suggests that criminal law is desirable because it will create—or strengthen—the right social arrangement.
For progressives, that means criminal law would be a social good when it benefits marginalized defendants and harms powerful defendants or defendants advancing regressive ends.
Criminal law and punishment might be worth supporting if they distribute the right way.
To be clear, we aren’t arguing that this is a good justification or that we would support criminal punishment because of its redistributive potential. We wouldn’t, and we don’t.
Rather, our suggestion is that understanding pro-criminalization arguments as reflecting a redistri-butionist logic should help us make sense of apparent contradictions in academic and public discourse.
We are not the first to suggest that progressives have a role in the making and maintenance of the carceral state. Indeed, several authors in the past decade have addressed this as a historical phenomenon.
Nor is this the first piece of scholarship to highlight critically the individual carceral issues—police violence, economic crimes, hate crimes, and gender-subordinating crimes—we describe in this Essay.
What we hope to contribute is a theory for why so many progressives still turn to criminal law despite all of the evidence that we as a society have overrelied on police and prisons for far too long. Redistribution certainly isn’t the only explanation. Indeed, many scholars and activists appear to justify their selective preference for criminal law in terms of retribution, expressivism, or deterrence.
But redistribution appears to have particular purchase in progressive circles as a vocabulary for justifying punitive politics. For scholars and activists committed to dismantling the carceral state, then, it is essential to grapple with these difficult areas and to recognize what does (or doesn’t) make them difficult.
We do not seek to suggest how progressives might solve social problems like systemic racism, gender subordination, or income inequality through noncarceral means. It remains to be seen whether the rich and increasing literature describing alternatives to the carceral state can ameliorate the pain and fury generated by crimes against marginalized people.
Instead, our project here is to surface and theorize the continued progressive commitment to criminal law, and to suggest that it should be recognized as a significant barrier to decarceral projects.
If progressives and decarcerationists are to be allies, they must see the fault lines in their alliance.
Further, we argue that the criminal system can’t do the redistributive work that some commentators imagine. Not only do we doubt that incarcerating brutal police officers will stop police brutality, but we also doubt that it will empower communities harmed by the police. Similarly, we doubt that incarcerating employers who steal their workers’ wages will redistribute wealth or remedy economic inequality.
Indeed, these carceral responses often serve to legitimate structural inequality by appearing to redistribute justice without doing anything about the larger systemic inequities that remain.
Perhaps even more troubling, these redistributive attempts actually may lead to more policing, prosecution, and punishment of the same marginalized communities that progressives hope to help.
Our argument unfolds in three Parts. In Part I, we trace the limits of anticarceral arguments and highlight the ways in which opposition to mass incarceration and overcriminalization often is heavily circumscribed—exceptions and carveouts abound. We describe a unifying theme in many of these progressive criminalization projects—a focus on redistribution. We examine competing conceptions of what redistribution means in this context (for example, shifting power, reallocating resources, and signaling social inclusion and valuation). In Part II, we offer a series of case studies to illustrate how progressive and left academics, activists, and lawmakers have justified punitive policies on redistributive grounds. Specifically, we examine the cases of police violence, economic crimes, hate crimes, and crimes of gender subordination. Finally in Part III, we step back and offer a critical take on redistributive arguments for criminal law. We argue that many redistributive arguments for criminal law rest on speculative empirical claims that lack real-world support. Further, we contend that the criminal system can’t redistribute in the egalitarian ways that some commentators imagine—criminal legal institutions are fundamentally regressive and tied to subordination. And, even if they somehow could advance some of the redistributive ends that their proponents suggest, our carceral system would remain objectionable. That is, the oppressive and inhumane aspects of the carceral state still would be oppressive and inhumane, even if the identity of the defendants or the politics associated with the institutions shifted.