DAGAN AND DORFMAN ON THE VALUE OF PRIVATE LAW

DAGAN AND DORFMAN ON THE VALUE OF PRIVATE LAW

Introduction

Hanoch Dagan and Avihay Dorfman believe that theoretical work on private law has become too polarized. Ranged on one side, there are those who “conceptualize private law as a set of regulatory strategies with no . . . unique moral significance.” 1 Hanoch Dagan & Avihay Dorfman, Just Relationships, 116 Colum. L. Rev. 1395, 1401 (2016). On the other side are those who associate private law with “values that dissociate it entirely from politics (broadly defined),” values that Dagan and Dorfman label “formal.” 2 Id. Dagan and Dorfman point out, masters of understatement that they are, that this is “a misleading dichotomy.” 3 Id. at 1400. There is plenty of habitable space between the two poles. In Just Relationships, they locate, and recommend, one possible intermediate position. With the “formal” (“traditional”) types they share the conviction that private law has some unique moral significance. With the “regulatory” (“critical”) types they share the view that private-law values cannot be dissociated entirely from politics. For, they claim, private-law values are the same “core liberal values” that are important outside private law too, including in public law. 4 Id. at 1414. It is merely that, for Dagan and Dorfman, private law contributes to the realization of those values in its own special way, so that it “stands on its own, distinc­tive ground.” 5 Id. at 1442.

I think Dagan and Dorfman would agree that their account of pri­vate law’s “distinctive ground” leaves their thinking closer to the “tradi­tional” pole than to its opposite. Specifically, they agree with the “tradition­alist” in portraying private law’s contribution as an (a) noninstrumental and (b) indispensable contribution to (c) a valuable frame­work of interper­sonal relationships, a framework the value of which also (d) does not rest on values other than the core liberal values that they list. The main difference between them and their “traditionalist” neigh­bors lies in which values are listed for the purpose of (d). For the “tradi­tionalists,” it is “formal freedom and equality.” 6 Id. at 1410, 1417. For Dagan and Dorfman, by contrast, it is “substan­tive freedom and equality.” 7 Id. at 1427, 1451. This shift from “for­mal” to “substantive” makes a lot of difference, in ways that Dagan and Dorfman elegantly explain. But it does not make the key difference that the full-blown “critical” theorist would apparently want it to make. It does not leave private law as “just another means to serve our public goals.” 8 Id. at 1410.

As well as admiring their complex and careful execution, I broadly sympathize with Dagan and Dorfman’s aims. I have myself complained about, and sought to escape, the strange polarization of theoretical work on private law. 9 See generally John Gardner, Tort Law and Its Theory, in The Cambridge Companion to Philosophy of Law (John Tasioulas ed., forthcoming 2018), http://www.dropbox.com/s/‍‌
otsl7dsvc7re7v0/torts-cambridgeencyclopedia.pdf?dl=1 [http://perma.cc/6BPG-UMRF].
I agree with Dagan and Dorfman, moreover, that private law is morally distinctive even though it cannot avoid being implicated in politics. 10 See generally John Gardner, What Is Tort Law For? Part 2. The Place of Distributive Justice, in Philosophical Foundations of the Law of Torts (John Oberdiek ed., 2014) (arguing private law does corrective justice but who it does corrective justice for is a question of distributive justice). And while I differ on some points that need not detain us here, I also share their wider liberal outlook on life, and hence many of their concrete judgments on how the law ought to deal with various problems. So we have much in common. Yet for my tastes, Dagan and Dorfman are still drawn too much toward the “traditionalist” pole. My instincts, if they have any general leaning at all, lean a little more toward those of the “critics.”

In particular I am a good deal less worried than Dagan and Dorfman are about the possibility that private law is “just another means to serve our public goals.” 11    Dagan & Dorfman, supra note 1, at 1410. Or rather, I would be less worried if we could drop the tendentious words “just another.” The main resistance to thinking of private law as a means to serve our public goals comes, I think, of a com­mon misunderstanding of what our public goals are, and hence of what it takes to serve them. Get that right, and we will see that thinking of pri­vate law as a means to serve our public goals does not mean regarding private law as anything like “public law in disguise.” 12 Id. at 1408 (quoting Leon Green, Tort Law Public Law in Disguise, 38 Tex. L. Rev. 1, 1–2 (1959)). If anything, the reverse is true. We will come to see that private law is in most ways a “garden-variety” 13 Id. at 1430. or vanilla case of law as an instrument of public policy, and public law is in large part a specialized adaptation of it. Dagan and Dorfman surrender too quickly to the same common misconceptions about public goals that lead some “critics” to think otherwise. They do not see the radical potential of their own liberal ideals as correctives for those misconceptions. The result is that they still show an excessively defen­sive reaction to the challenge of the most reductive “critics.” They still erect too many of the “traditionalist’s” contrived, overblown, and high-maintenance fortifications against the embarrassingly paltry attacks of an ill-equipped but noisy army of (what shall we call them?) public policy technicians.

It is unlikely that a short response such as this could spell out these claims satisfactorily, never mind bear them out. Barring some short remarks toward the end, therefore, this Response is limited to exposing the “contrived, overblown, and high-maintenance fortifications” that Dagan and Dorfman inherit from the “traditionalists.” That exposure can best be achieved by reflecting, one by one, on the four principal motifs of Dagan and Dorfman’s portrayal of private law. To recapitulate and abbreviate, they are (a) noninstrumentality, (b) indispensability, (c) relationality, and (d) value-specificity.

I. Noninstrumentality

For Dagan and Dorfman, “private law is valuable beyond its contin­gent . . . benefits: It is intrinsically valuable.” 14 Id. at 1397. Intrinsic value is contrasted with instrumental value, which, we may infer, is the value that lies in the “contingent benefits” of whatever possesses it. Yet the word “contingent” here is misleading. It may make you think that Dagan and Dorfman see the intrinsic value of private law as entirely unconditional, as holding whatever else may hold. Although they do say once that private law has “value in and of itself,” 15 Id. at 1412. it seems they do not really see it that way. They see the intrinsic value of private law as derivative, derivative of the value of the “interpersonal relationships” 16 Id. at 1398. to which it contributes. They claim that private law is necessary for the existence of these valuable interper­sonal relationships, 17 See infra Part II. but wisely, they do not say that it is sufficient. In par­ticular, they do not say that private law contributes to valuable relationships irrespective of which doctrines private law contains. In later sec­tions of their article, they note various respects in which private law doc­trines could be more or less successful by Dagan-and-Dorfman stand­ards. Presumably, then, private law doctrines could be corrupt or dere­lict, adding little to the value of anything, maybe adding only to the mal­for­mation (e.g., the “substantive inequality”) of relationships on which they bear. 18 I take it that Dagan and Dorfman would not run the “definitional stop” argument according to which, if certain doctrines are corrupt or derelict, they do not form part of private law. Much that Dagan and Dorfman say suggests that, on the contrary, they are mainstream legal positivists who think that “[t]he existence of [private] law is one thing: its merits or demerits are another.” Those words are from John Austin, The Province of Jurisprudence Determined 278 (London, John Murray 1832) (on file with the Columbia Law Review). They are repeatedly echoed by Dagan and Dorfman: “[S]ome or all these doctrines may currently fail to sufficiently limit this gap,” Dagan & Dorfman, supra note 1, at 1426; “private-law doctrines . . . may undermine these commitments,” id. at 1428; and “these doctrines manifest a (perhaps overly) cautious approach,” id. at 1456. This shows that the reference to contingency by Dagan and Dorfman is a red herring. Intrinsic value is not the same as noncontingent value. To get with the Dagan-and-Dorfman program, one must distin­guish instrumental from intrinsic value in some other way.

Dagan and Dorfman do not make it easy to do so. They use a bewildering variety of verbs to capture what they take to be the kind of contribution that private law makes to valuable interpersonal relation­ships, by virtue of which it has intrinsic value. It “construct[s]” relation­ships; 19 Dagan & Dorfman, supra note 1, at 1397. it “forge[s] and sustain[s]” them; 20 Id. at 1398. it “structures” them; 21 Id. at 1406. it “marshal[s]” their rights and obligations; 22 Id. at 1410. it “sets [them] up”; 23 Id. at 1413. it “consti­tut[es]” and “authoriz[es]” them; 24 Id. at 1416. it “uphold[s]” them; 25 Id. at 1422. it “casts” them in a certain form; 26 Id. at 1430. it “establish[es]” and “facilitate[s]” them; 27 Id. it “secur[es]” them. 28 Id. at 1436. For anyone who imagined that the instru­mental value of something would be value that it contributes by virtue of its causal consequences (which is how the expression is used by many philosophers 29 See, e.g., Christine Korsgaard, Creating the Kingdom of Ends 251–52 (1996); Joseph Raz, The Morality of Freedom 177 (1986); Shelly Kagan, Rethinking Intrinsic Value, 2 J. Ethics 278, 281 (1998); Larry Temkin, Equality, Priority, and the Levelling Down Objection, in The Ideal of Equality 129 (Matthew Clayton & Andrew Williams eds., 2000). ), some entries on this list are disorientating. My breakfast sustains me until lunchtime. My keyfob facilitates my entry to the building. My IT guy sets up my new software. My soldering iron forges a new connection. My parasol casts a big shadow. These are various causal consequences, by virtue of which value is transmitted to whatever has them. My parasol is instrumental in providing me with shade, my IT guy is instrumental in getting my computer updated, etc. What, then, is sup­posed to be noninstrumental about private law?

In some of the passages just quoted, Dagan and Dorfman are strug­gling for the right word to capture the noninstrumentality they have in mind. The word they finally seem to settle on, late in the article, is “constitutes.” Private law, they say, is “constitutive” of some relationships. 30 Dagan & Dorfman, supra note 1, at 1449. Although the idea of constitution is rife with philosophi­cal difficulties, many borne of its connection with the idea of identity, 31 For a good introduction, see generally Ryan Wasserman, The Constitution Question, 38 Noûs 693 (2004) (addressing “the question of what conditions are necessary and jointly sufficient for one object to constitute another”). it is tolerably clear that constituting is a way of contributing other than by way of causal consequences. A constitutes B only if A is the whole or a part of B, or (as Dagan and Dorfman also put it) only if A is “integral” to B. 32 Dagan & Dorfman, supra note 1, at 1424. As its name suggests, the constitution of any legal system part-constitutes that system. The norms of the constitution do not exert their hold over the other norms of the system from without but rather from within. In much the same way, ordinary legal norms part-constitute cer­tain social roles, including not only some that owe their existence to the law (being a trustee or a freeholder or a plaintiff) but also some that would already exist apart from the law (being a parent, an adult, an employee, a rescuer, a giver of consent, a self-defender, etc.). In the latter cases the law constitutes the role, to the extent that it does, mainly by contributing extra determinacy to the role’s already-constitutive (set of) norms. Legal norms thereby become integral to the role. It seems that this is the kind of contribution that, for Dagan and Dorfman, private law makes to the “interpersonal relationships” that interest them. Perhaps that is what they are trying to convey in their obscurely formulated remark that private law “participate[s] in constructing core categories of interpersonal relationships around their underlying normative ideals.” 33 Id. at 1450. Here, the authors are almost quoting from Hanoch Dagan, The Utopian Promise of Private Law, 66 U. Toronto L.J. 392, 400 (2016), but I did not find any additional illumination of the remark’s intended meaning in that article.

It is, however, a further step from here to the conclusion that private law contributes constitutively to these relationships “quite apart from” any instrumental contribution it may make. 34 Dagan & Dorfman, supra note 1, at 1412. I have argued elsewhere, at some length, that only instrumentally successful legal norms can be constitutively successful. 35 See generally John Gardner, What is Tort Law For? Part 1. The Place of Corrective Justice, 30 Law & Phil. 1, 31 (2011). My argument lends extra support to the position defended by Shelly Kagan in Rethinking Intrinsic Value. See Kagan, supra note 29, at 281. Only a legal norm that helps people to do what they ought to do anyway, quite apart from that norm, can help to deter­mine (add determinacy to) what people ought to do. Only a law that helps people to be good parents, for example, can help to settle what counts as being a good parent. The argument, in brief outline, is this: Legitimate legal norms are those that help us to do what we ought to do anyway, quite apart from the law. One way in which they can help us to do this is by making it more determinate what we ought to do, reducing doubts and confusions and conflicts, and thereby reducing the risk of error and waste. When legal norms achieve this much, they change what we ought to do over a range of cases, namely, the formerly indeterminate cases now rendered determinate by the law. This is a constitutive change to what we ought to do. It builds, however, on an instrumental achieve­ment. The law is able to make the relevant constitutive change to what we ought to do only because by making that change, it helps us to do what we ought to do anyway, quite apart from the change.

If sound, this argument would explain why Dagan and Dorfman are still tempted to use instrumental vocabulary (“forge,” “sustain,” “facili­tate,” “secure,” etc.) even when the contribution they are talking about is supposed to be a noninstrumental one. Foregrounding private law’s instrumentality does not compromise the thesis that private law has intrinsic value. Quite the contrary. One must foreground private law’s instrumentality if one wants to explain how it can be that private law has intrinsic value. The implication is that Dagan and Dorfman should fur­ther tone down some of what they say about private law’s intrinsic value. They should not merely eliminate any suggestion that this intrinsic value is unconditional value. They should go further and eliminate any sugges­tion that it is value that private law has independent of private law’s instrumental value. In doing so, they cannot but tone down the bold pic­ture they paint of private law’s distinctiveness.

In these last remarks I took it for granted that, if private law contrib­utes noninstrumentally to valuable relationships, then private law inher­its intrinsic value via that contribution. But of course further conditions need to be satisfied before that is true. First, the relationships in question need to be not just valuable but intrinsically valuable. There needs to be intrinsic value in them that can be inherited by private law. Second, the constitutive contribution of private law needs to be a contribution to that very intrinsic value.

Consider the tiny cogs (they are called “pinions”) in my watch. They partly constitute my watch and contribute in many ways to its value as a watch (by helping to make it operational, accurate, durable, wearable, adjustable, reparable, quiet, etc.). But that makes the cogs intrinsi­cally valuable only if the watch itself is intrinsically valuable. If the watch itself is a mere instrument, then its constituents, as its constituents, inherit only instrumental value from the watch by their contribution to it. And even if the watch has intrinsic value (e.g., as a thing of beauty or a family heirloom or part of my carefully curated watch collection), it does not follow that the pinions contribute to that value. Maybe the watch’s intrin­sic value would be unaffected by the loss of instrumentality in the watch that the failure or loss of a pinion would cause. Maybe the watch was, for example, the one that saved my father from a bullet during the war, such that repairing its warped mechanism and getting it working again would restore its instrumental value but do nothing for, or maybe even deplete, its intrinsic value. If at some point, unbeknownst to anyone, a pinion were to fall out of the case and be lost, the intrinsic value of the watch would be unaffected. Although the pinion was a constituent of the watch, it contributed nothing to its intrinsic value. Its only role lay in a possible revival of the watch’s instrumental value.

Dagan and Dorfman do not stop to discuss whether and how the interpersonal relationships that private law helps to constitute are them­selves intrinsically valuable. If friendship, parenthood, and the like are our foreground examples, we may think it obvious that interpersonal relationships are not mere instruments (although even these examples are more problematic than they seem). 36 See Elinor Mason, Do Consequentialists Have One Thought Too Many?, 2 Ethical Theory & Moral Prac. 243, 247–48 (1999) (challenging the more romantic view in Bernard Williams, Persons, Character and Morality, in The Identities of Persons (Amélie Oksenberg Rorty ed., 1976)). But does it seem so obvious with “bailment, suretyship, and fiduciary” relationships, 37 Dagan & Dorfman, supra note 1, at 1449. three which are mentioned by Dagan and Dorfman as relationships constituted, in part or in whole, by private law? Dagan and Dorfman do not explain what exactly they take to be the intrinsic value of relationships such as these, or indeed any others. However, they do make clear—even in the title of their article—which value they take private law to contribute to such rela­tionships, by virtue of which private law counts as intrinsically valuable. Private law helps (constitutively) to make such relationships just. So it seems reasonable to suppose that, whatever else about such relationships they may regard as intrinsically valuable, Dagan and Dorfman regard them as intrinsically valuable inasmuch as justice prevails in them.

Dagan and Dorfman are far from alone if they take the view that acting justly toward others is intrinsically valuable. It seems to be a com­mon view. 38 For recent evidence, by both example and testimony, see Justin Klocksiem, Two Conceptions of Justice, 14 J. Moral Phil. (forthcoming 2017) (manuscript at 18), http://booksandjournals.brillonline.com.ezproxy.cul.columbia.edu/content/journals/10.1163/17455243-46810055 [http://perma.cc/S6PJ-J7PD]. But it is unclear where it gets its purchase. One possible explanation is that the analytic value of acting justly is mistaken for intrinsic value. The thought is that if the value of acting justly were only instrumental, it would vary from case to case. Sometimes acting justly would not be valuable at all, because it would not have any good causal consequences. So to preserve the analyticity of justice’s value, it is thought, that value cannot be instrumental. 39 This line of thought is what drives the dialogue between Socrates and Glaucon in Plato, The Republic bk. II (G. R. F. Ferrari ed., Tom Griffith trans., Cambridge Univ. Press 2000) (c. 381 B.C.E.). But that doesn’t follow. It is equally possible (and often true) that when the act would not have any good causal consequences, it would also not be just. If punishing a crimi­nal offender does not prevent any crime, for example, it is not just. One may disagree with this claim about punishment, but that is not important here. What is important here is that the claim is intelligible. It intelligibly preserves the analyticity of justice’s value (no justice if no good is done) without adding any hint of intrinsic value (the good in question, the pre­vention of crime, is instrumentally served by the just act).

Another possible explanation lies with Rawls’s famous association of norms of justice with “deontology,” or “the priority of the right over the good.” 40 See John Rawls, A Theory of Justice 30–31 (1971) (discussing deontology and priority of right, respectively). Often overlooked is that Rawls limits his argument for that association, such as it is, to his own norms of justice (the ones applying to institutions in what Rawls calls the basic structure of society) and does not purport to extend it to principles of justice generally. 41 Id. at 7–9. Its extension to those norms of justice that regulate what Dagan and Dorfman call “horizontal” relationships 42 Dagan & Dorfman, supra note 1, passim. would arguably be the hardest of all to engineer. 43 For extended discussion of the difficulty, see G.A. Cohen, Rescuing Justice and Equality 27–150 (2008). But even if the extension could be engineered, it is far from straightforward to convert the thesis that norms of justice are deontological into the the­sis that doing justice has intrinsic value. If the rightness of doing the just thing does not depend on the good that is thereby done, then it is true that this rightness cannot be defended by pointing to its instrumental value. By the same token, however, it cannot be defended by pointing to its intrinsic value. That is because for a deontologist about justice, the rightness of doing the just thing does not depend on its value at all.

Whether doing the just thing has intrinsic value is a further question. Rawls did not address it. 44 Rawls did return to the question of “the good of justice” in A Theory of Justice. Rawls, supra note 40, at 513–87. However, his discussion there concerns the intrinsic value of each of us having and acting on a sense of justice, not the intrinsic value of institutions in the basic structure acting justly. In fact, in as much as he did point to any value in institutions acting in line with his own “two principles of justice,” it was entirely instrumental value. It was the value of protecting people from some of the worst risks that they could face once they become socially organized. Protection against such risks is famously what the parties to the “original position” are motivated to seek for themselves. 45 Id. at 14. How this instrumentality of user motivation is meant to interplay with Rawls’ deon­tology about justice is one of the great mysteries of his work. But if one thing is certain, it is that one cannot conclude merely from the deontol­ogy that doing the just thing is ever, let alone always, of intrinsic value.

I am not saying that Dagan and Dorfman make this last move. It is hard to know what move they are making on this front. But whatever move they are making, it is too quick. Even if we can agree that the rela­tionships that interest Dagan and Dorfman have intrinsic value, we should be careful not to assume that the mere fact that they are justly conducted forms part of it. One may think, for example, that when the intrinsic value of such relationships is riding high, the question of how justly they are being conducted doesn’t arise. 46 This point was central to Michael Sandel’s famous critique of Rawls in Liberalism and the Limits of Justice, in which he presents justice “as a remedial virtue, whose moral advantage consists in the repair it works on fallen conditions.” Michael Sandel, Liberalism and the Limits of Justice 32 (1998). Notice the vaguely instrumental word “works.” Notice also the ease with which this way of demarcating the business of justice accommodates the main work of the courts in private law cases. For one may think, developing the thought that motivates those in Rawls’s original position, that the role of norms of justice in such relationships is to protect people against risks of mistreatment that arise, inter alia, from breaches of the other norms (perhaps not norms of justice) that help to constitute their relationships’ intrinsic value. Norms of justice are a fail-safe mechanism that helps to stop a hemorrhage of intrinsic value from turning into an instrumental catastrophe. If that is so, then private law’s contribution to the justice of the relationships is not a contribution to their intrinsic value, and private law inherits no intrinsic value from them.

II. Indispensability

It is tempting to think that whatever is integral to something (constitutive of it) is also indispensable to it. But that is a mistake. Many integral parts of modern household appliances are over-engineered (sometimes to build in their obsolescence) and could readily be replaced with something simpler. The same goes, probably, for many integral parts of modern government. The alternative would sometimes be an improve­ment on what it replaces, but that is not crucial to this point. Sometimes one could still muddle along, albeit not optimally, with a piece of old hosepipe or an eager bunch of amateurs. These are cases in which we are hoping to maintain sheer instrumentality by replacing a part, but that too is not crucial to this point. Even constituents of an intrinsically valuable thing that contribute to its intrinsic value may be replaced by new constituents, sometimes adding to the intrinsic value of the whole, some­times subtracting from it, but sometimes neither.

Take the constituents of your own life. Over time they change. Indie rock may have been your passion in your teens, then a few years later it was mountaineering, then independent travel in remote lands, but these days you throw yourself into home improvements. These are all constitu­ents of your life that, over the years, have filled similar spaces in it. They have contributed to the value of your life not merely instrumentally, i.e., not only by their causal consequences. Home improvements may improve your living conditions and your house’s resale potential, while saving you money on contractors. That may have been what got you started on it. But these days that is no longer the whole, or even the main, point. There is also your own engagement in the activity, which is lending, as people often like to put it, extra meaning to your life, enriching your life with new skills and accomplishments, perhaps even new virtues. Yet as the history of your life shows, that does not mean that your life is deprived of meaning without it. Few, if any, value-contributing constituents of a valuable life are irreplaceable, however it may seem at the time. 47 Returning for a moment to Sandel’s Liberalism and the Limits of Justice: Sandel trades throughout on the thought that what is more constitutive of our lives (and our selves) is less dispensable. He doesn’t offer any serious argument that I can find. See id. at 179–83. Remember the mountaineering years?

Dagan and Dorfman do not conflate their claim that private law con­tributes intrinsically valuable constituents of intrinsically valuable relation­ships with their claim that this contribution is indispensable or irreplaceable. But nor do they put as much effort as they should into pre­venting the two claims from becoming conflated in the mind of the reader. 48 This risk comes partly of the wider phenomenon that Fred Feldman captures in the title, and treats in the text, of his classic article Hyperventilating About Intrinsic Value, 2 J. Ethics 339, 339 (1998). The threat that private law’s value will otherwise be rendered “contingent” is used to advance both claims in quick succession, and the expressions “irreducible role” 49 Dagan & Dorfman, supra note 1, at 1422. and “integral role,” 50 Id. at 1424. again used in quick succession, are too open to being read as synonymous. And then there is the unexplained segue from private law’s being “constitutive” to private law’s being “crucial.” 51 Id. at 1449. Nevertheless, on closer inspection, Dagan and Dorfman do provide arguments (or sketches of arguments) for the indis­pensability of private law’s contribution that are quite distinct from any­thing they say about its intrinsic value. These arguments have their appeal. My worry is that they lend support to two rival pictures of what the indispensability of private law’s contribution comes down to.

To see the space for equivocation in what Dagan and Dorfman say, consider their concluding remark: “Private law is indispensable. Only such a legal order can establish frameworks of interaction among free and equal individuals who respect each other for the persons they actu­ally are.” 52 Id. at 1460. The “can” here is the main problem. The word is, as J.L. Austin memorably put it, “constitutionally iffy.” 53 J.L. Austin, Ifs and Cans, in Philosophical Papers 205, 205 (J.O. Urmson & Geoffrey Warnock eds., Oxford Univ. Press 3d ed. 1979) (1960). There is no such thing as what is possible full stop; there is only what range of possibility is opened up when certain actualities, but not others, are held constant in the imagination. There is only what is psychologically possible, humanly possible, physically possible, conceptually possible, logically possible, etc., where the qualifying adjective (which we often infer from context) is there to fix some constants, and thus by implication, to allow some variables.

So which set of constants, you may wonder, are Dagan and Dorfman fixing when they say that only private law can do what (in their view) it does for just relationships? At the start of their article, it seems to be something like logical or conceptual possibility that they have in mind. “Since private law is the law of our horizontal interactions,” they say, “its roles cannot be properly performed by any other legal field.” 54 Dagan & Dorfman, supra note 1, at 1398. No other premises are stated. So what should we make of this “since,” if not that it is the “since” of logical or conceptual necessity, or entailment, blocking the logical or conceptual possibility of private law’s displacement? One may initially understand Dagan and Dorfman, then, to be saying this: The fact that private law is the law of horizontal interactions entails that no other law establishes frameworks for horizontal interactions. If any law establishes frameworks for horizontal interactions, that makes it private law. It cannot, logically or conceptually, be otherwise. We may then corre­spondingly read the word “properly” to mean “properly speaking” or something like that. Take away private law and, properly speaking, no law establishes frameworks for horizontal interactions. For, properly speaking, any law that did so would be private law, in just the same way that, properly speaking, any tiny rotating wheel of metal that helped to transmit motion to the escapement in my watch would be a pinion.

Yet the word “properly” already sows seeds of doubt in the reader’s mind. And so it should. Later in the paper, a different kind of propriety, and a different range of possibility, seems to be what Dagan and Dorfman have in mind:

[T]he responsibility for upholding just horizontal relationships requires a legal apparatus and cannot be fully delegated to social norms. To be sure, social norms may suffice insofar as they respond to the dictates of just relationships and are taken to have an obligatory nature so that they in fact govern people’s interpersonal relationships. But this is only because they would then be law-like. If, however, this is not the case—which is likely given our contemporary social environment—relying on social norms amounts, at best, to an indirect and opaque endorsement of private-law libertarianism. This is deeply problematic because it would threaten the liberal state’s commitment to individual self-determination and substantive equality. There is, therefore, a clear role for law in upholding and promoting just relationships. 55 Id. at 1421–22.

Here we find the “can” of moral acceptability or legitimacy. It is more like a “may.” That social norms would do the relationship-upholding work of private law is not logically or conceptually impossible, it turns out, but only morally forbidden. How do we know that it is not logically or conceptually impossible? Because if something is logically or conceptually impossible, the question of whether it is morally forbidden cannot arise. So this is surely a rival picture of private law’s indispensabil­ity. I will assume that it is the picture that Dagan and Dorfman finally endorse.

If so, it is a picture that includes surprising concessions. First, it allows that social norms compete with private law to make the contribu­tion that private law makes to our interpersonal relationships. Second, it allows that social norms might usurp the contribution of private law com­pletely if they were suitably “law-like.” This suggests to me that private law is not after all morally indispensable. All that we need is something that is suitably like private law and then it is morally open to us to dispense with private law. No surprise there: All I need to give meaning to my life after my mountaineering days are over is something suitably like mountain­eering . . . how about home improvements? True, the work of private law might well be done worse if left entirely to social norms. That indeed strikes Dagan and Dorfman as “likely” and leaves them pointing to a “clear role for [private] law” in “our contemporary social environment.” 56 Id. at 1422. But a merely clear role, one that is premised on a mere likeli­hood, a likelihood that in turn is relativized to a certain social environ­ment, does not amount to a very robust kind of indispensability. In fact, to my ears, it makes the use of the word “indispensable” seem hyperbolic.

By the same token, it provides the “critics,” or some of them, with a possible answer to Dagan and Dorfman’s charge that they make pri­vate law seem too easily dispensable or replaceable. What stops the “critic” from saying, with Dagan and Dorfman, that, while there are other possible ways to do what private law does, private law in all likeli­hood remains the best way to do it in our contemporary social environ­ment, such that not doing it that way would, for the here and now, most likely be a morally unacceptable move? Dagan and Dorfman may reply that the “critic” probably means an instrumental “best” when they mean a con­stitutive “best.” That, however, is a different issue. There is nothing in what Dagan and Dorfman say about private law’s indispensability to suggest that regarding private law as an instrument is at odds with, or indeed has any other implications for, regarding it as indispensable. In the passage quoted above, recall, Dagan and Dorfman talk about the competition between private law and social norms in “upholding and promoting just relationships.” Even if upholding just relationships were somehow a noninstrumental way of contributing to them (which I doubt), the same clearly cannot be said of promoting just relationships. 57 Indeed, Philip Pettit chooses the word “promote” as the one best suited to expressing what a consequentialist would have us do with value. Philip Pettit, Consequentialism, in A Companion to Ethics 230 passim (Peter Singer ed., 1993). So for the purpose of this passage, and more generally for the purpose of thinking about their defense of private law’s indispensability, Dagan and Dorfman might as well be treated as if they too were instrumentalists. And why not? If a pinion in my excellent watch is the only one of its kind, and nobody any longer has the skill to manufacture me a new one, then the pinion makes an utterly indispensable contribution to my watch’s continuing excellence—even though there may be no intrinsic value in either the watch or the pinion.

III. Relationality

Dagan and Dorfman also overplay the relationality of private law. They do not notice, or at least do not note, an important distinction between a stricter and a looser sense in which duties may be relational. 58 In this section, I sketch a position that is developed in more detail in the first chapter of my forthcoming book. See John Gardner, From Personal Life to Private Law (forthcoming 2018). When duties are relational in the strict sense, the value of the relation­ship to which they belong forms part of the case for their existence. But when they are relational only in the loose sense, the value of the relation­ship to which they belong plays no such role. Although there is a relationship to which they belong, the case for their existence is independent of the value of that relationship. Private law need only con­tain duties that are relational in the loose sense. Dagan and Dorfman give the impression that its duties are also relational in the strict sense. By so doing, Dagan and Dorfman bind private law more closely than it should be bound to the value of relationships, and in the process, artifi­cially inflate both its value and, I think, the distinctiveness of its value.

To understand the difference between strict and loose relationality, think about the modern history of the tort of negligence. Think in particular about the basis of the “duty of care,” breach of which is the ingredient of the tort after which the whole tort is named. This duty was once regarded as existing only between people in certain enumerated special relationships—doctor and patient, lawyer and client, carrier and passenger, host and guest, parent and child, teacher and pupil, etc. But by a gradual process, culminating in the 1932 decision of the House of Lords in Donoghue v. Stevenson, a general rationale for the incidence of the duty emerged, supposedly revealing the common thread running through all the special relationships with which the duty had hitherto been associated. 59 Donoghue v. Stevenson [1932] AC 562 (HL) 564 (appeal taken from Scot.) (extending the duty owed by manufacturers to include reasonable care toward all consumers). Lord Atkin famously wrote:

You must take reasonable care to avoid acts or omissions which you can reasonably foresee would be likely to injure your neighbour. Who, then, in law, is my neighbour? The answer seems to be—persons who are so closely and directly affected by my act that I ought reasonably to have them in contemplation as being so affected when I am directing my mind to the acts or omissions which are called in question. 60 Id. at 580.

One reason why these words represent such a watershed in the his­tory of tort law is that they rule out one possible rationale for inclusion of any given relationship on the “enumerated list” that had previously been used to settle the incidence of the duty of care. Inclusion on the list is not, or is no longer, to be rationalized by pointing to the value of the included relationships. Why not? It is not that no relationship at all holds between plaintiff and defendant in Lord Atkin’s explanation. The point, rather, is that the explanation does not depend on there being any value in that relationship. Indeed, it is, so far as Lord Atkin characterizes it, a relationship that we should all want to avoid. It is the relationship that holds between two people merely by virtue of the fact that the actions of the one put the other at risk. It is true that the entries on the previous “enumerated list” are all still likely to be covered by Lord Atkin’s characterization (that is why he doesn’t need to overrule the old cases to get where he is going). People in the relationships on the list are often in a strong position to put each other at risk. The question is: Why do we care enough about this fact that we hold the parties to such relationships to be under duties of care to each other? Here is a previously possible answer, now ruled out by Lord Atkin: We care about supporting people’s valuable relationships; upholding (and in the process adding determi­nacy to) constituent duties of those relationships is one way to do it. Here is the new answer, the one approved by Lord Atkin: We care about protecting people from the risks that they pose to each other; worse luck that they happen to stand to each other in such a way as to pose such risks (and worse luck even when their so standing toward each other is a side effect of an otherwise valuable relationship).

The previously possible answer made the duty of care relational in the strict sense. The new answer leaves it relational only in the loose sense. True, in the words of Dagan and Dorfman, the new answer still “addresses our interpersonal interactions by marshaling rights and obligations that take a relational form.” 61 Dagan & Dorfman, supra note 1, at 1410. The point is only that, in the post-1932 law of negligence, 62 In the United States a similar development occurred earlier in MacPherson v. Buick Motor Co., 111 N.E. 1050 (N.Y. 1916). the existence of a valuable relationship between the rightholder and the dutybearer does not form part of the case for doing the marshaling. That is not to say that there is nothing valuable in being protected by legal rights and duties. When such rights and duties are legitimately created and upheld, they have the value that they are instrumental in the protection of the rightholder. But those rights and duties are created and upheld at the conclusion of an argu­ment, in the premises of which no other valuable relationship between the rightholder and the dutybearer figures. Everything in the premises of the argument is consistent with the possibility that nothing would have been lost had the two of them never crossed paths with each other at all.

As we just noticed, Dagan and Dorfman accurately report the loose relationality of private law duties. They are duties owed by one person to another, who is the rightholder, and that is enough to make them rela­tional in the loose sense. But Dagan and Dorfman, it seems to me, tend to jump from here straight to the thesis that private law duties are rela­tional in the strict sense too. They speak of private law’s “implicit norma­tive promise of securing just relationships,” where the justice of a relationship is taken to be not only valuable but also to be part of a case for people to enter into it. 63 Dagan & Dorfman, supra note 1, at 1397. They mention the contractual case in which (I roughly agree) the law “enable[s] free persons . . . [to] set and pursue their own purposes interdependently,” 64 Id. at 1404 (quoting Arthur Ripstein, Force and Freedom: Kant’s Legal and Political Philosophy 107–08 (2009)). Dagan and Dorfman disagree with Ripstein’s interpreta­tion of “free” but do not appear to depart otherwise from Ripstein’s explanation of the value of contract. See id. at 1412 (“[W]hile a contractual promise may enable both promisee and promisor to realize their respective desirable goals, the very manner in which the contractual transaction achieves this is of value, too, for it requires those who utilize it to recognize each other as parties to a joint endeavor.”). or more generally to create valuable relationships for themselves. There is strict relationality in the law of contract, to be sure, and also in fiduciary law, and even perhaps in some of the law of torts. But it does not permeate the whole of private law. So even if it is true that “[o]nly private law can forge and sustain the variety of frameworks for interdependent interpersonal relationships that allow us to form and lead the conception of our lives,” 65 Id. at 1398. it does not fol­low, and it is not true, that all of private law shares, or helps to perform, this task. Does Lord Atkin make any “promise of securing just relation­ships”? No. Or at any rate, not as those words are most naturally inter­preted. He promises to help to secure us against the risks of certain relationships characterized by riskiness, should we unfortunately find ourselves in them. That is very different from promising to secure that, fortunately, we (can) have these relationships. The law of negligence in tort could not be more different, in this respect, from the law of contract or the law of trusts, in which the (claimed) value of forming and maintaining contractual and fiduciary relationships, or at least being able to do so, is argumentatively central.

The examples of the law of contract and the law of trusts show clearly that the valuable relationships on which strictly relational duties depend need not be intrinsically valuable. “[E]nabl[ing] free persons to . . . set and pursue their own purposes interdependently” 66 Id. at 1404 (quoting Arthur Ripstein, Force and Freedom: Kant’s Legal and Political Philosophy 107 (2009)). is an instru­mental task for the law of contract if ever there was one. The examples also help us to see that the distinction I am drawing between loosely and strictly relational duties does not map onto, or indeed have any connec­tion with, the distinction that I drew earlier between relationships that “owe their existence to the law” and those that “would already exist apart from the law.” 67 See supra text accompanying notes 30–33. Contracts exist apart from the law and are merely recog­nized and upheld (under limited circumstances) by the law. Trusts not so. They are the law’s canny invention. So valuable relationships may be the law’s invention or otherwise. A duty is strictly relational when the value of a relationship, other than the value of someone’s acquiring and having the duty, plays a part in the argument for the existence of the duty.

Even when the relationship is entirely the law’s invention, the relationship’s value may figure in the argument for including certain constituent duties within it. That is how things are with “bailment, suretyship, and fiduciary [relationships]” 68 Dagan & Dorfman, supra note 1, at 1449. and the duties that form part of them. It is not how things are with the relationships of right and duty that exist in large parts of the modern law of torts. Recognizing that difference helps us to deflate the inflationary Dagan-and-Dorfman pro­posal that private law has a “commitment to the ideal of just relation­ships” 69 Id. at 1400, 1427. that can differentiate it from other parts of the law. The offending word is “ideal.” It leads one to expect that the relationships of private law will all be worth having and pursuing, at least in the eyes of private law. But in fact, as Lord Atkin explains, in many cases private law, with its marshaling of rights and duties, only attempts to protect one against the dangers of relationships that may, so far as private law is con­cerned, have nothing to be said in favor of entering into them. The best one can say of them is that at least private law provided one with some protection from their worst dangers—yes, in a “relational form” (in the form of marshaled rights and duties) but no, not on the strength of any positive case for “upholding,” 70 Id. at 1422. “promoting,” 71 Id. “sustain[ing],” 72 Id. at 1411. or “facilitating” 73 Id. at 1416. the relationships themselves.

IV. Value-specificity

So far I have said little about the particular values that Dagan and Dorfman find to be the animating values of private law, namely, those of “substantive freedom and equality.” 74        Id. at 1451. Although the point is not spelled out, the most natural reading of what they write is that they regard private law as answering to these values only. But why would they so regard it? The answer is not obvious. It could be because (i) for Dagan and Dorfman these are the only values that exist; or (ii) there are other values that exist, but for Dagan and Dorfman these are the only values that the law as a whole answers to; or (iii) there are other values that the law as a whole answers to, but private law is distinctive in answering only to these two. In setting out the Dagan and Dorfman position toward the start of this Response, I associated them with position (iii). But I was sticking my neck out in doing so. There is little evidence in their article to support that association.

Position (iii) seems the most likely candidate for Dagan and Dorfman to endorse, partly because it is difficult to imagine that they would sign up to either (i) or (ii), which are wildly implausible. Nobody, be they ever so liberal-minded, should think that the law has no business guiding people toward worthwhile pursuits and away from worthless ones. The law (and indeed every person) has reason to do whatever will help people avoid wronging each other, to have healthy personal relationships, to avoid wasting their lives and destroying their self-respect, to cultivate their virtues, tastes, and skills, to overcome their limitations, and many other things besides. Of course, liberal-minded people tend to agree that it matters greatly whether the worthwhile pursuits toward which the law steers people are embraced freely by those people and not foisted upon them. We should all care that everyone has a decent range of worthwhile options and enjoys a sufficient degree of independence in selecting among those options. In the name of maintaining the element of independence, some suboptimality in any given person’s selection often has to be tolerated. Yet the main implication of these points for the law is surely not that they shorten the list of values that the law exists to serve. Quite the contrary: They add an extra value, that of freedom, to the list. What they subtract in the process are not values that the law may serve, but rather acceptable ways of bringing those values into people’s lives. The value of freedom affects the means by which the other values on the wider list are to be served. For they are to be served in ways that do not disproportionately trammel freedom. That is of particular importance to the law because the law is by its nature prone to clumsi­ness and tends disproportionately to trammel freedom wherever it goes. It is therefore to be used only subject to various constraints and inhibi­tions, such as the harm principle, the various maxims of the rule of law, the rights of free speech, free association and free conscience, and so forth.

It may be protested that this is already a niche “liberal perfectionist”—I prefer to say “liberal imperfectionist”—view. 75 It is close to that of Joseph Raz in The Morality of Freedom, in which he dubs it a “perfectionist” view. Raz, supra note 29, at 424. Michael Walzer persuasively suggests that “imperfectionist” would have been a better label to use, given the emphasis that Raz places on allowing latitude for suboptimality. Walzer, The Imperfectionist, New Republic, Dec. 7, 1987, at 30. This is not the way, for example, that the “traditionalists” of private law theory think about the place of freedom in our lives and in our law. But Dagan and Dorfman themselves appear to be liberal imperfectionists. In connection with the law of contract, they speak of the freedom of “both promisee and promisor to realize their respective desirable goals,” 76 Dagan & Dorfman, supra note 1, at 1412 (emphasis added). and they worry in tort law about “the injurer’s autonomy to pursue worthwhile ends.” 77 Id. at 1435 (emphasis added). So they place emphasis on the desirability of goals and the worth­whileness of ends, as well as on the freedom of the law’s subjects to pur­sue them.

What is not so clear is to what extent this liberal imperfectionism affects their thinking about the value of private law. When the issue appears to be on the point of being taken up, it almost immediately slips away again. Dagan and Dorfman say that working through the implica­tions of their ideals “requires an elaborate theory of autonomy and an account as to what choices make a person’s life go well.” 78 Id. at 1419. But they promptly move on to classifying choices according to the way the choice figures in the chooser’s life, content-independently, ignoring the cross-cutting, content-dependent question of the value of the option that is being chosen. So they never seem to quite reach the question of whether private law is supposed to help us make better choices, or merely choices that mean a lot to us, self-constituting choices, life-affecting choices, etc.

Inasmuch as Dagan and Dorfman do say things that suggest that private law takes an interest in our making better choices, the applicable currency of value still appears to be (equal) freedom. The best choice for anyone, the one that counts as serving a desirable goal, is the one in which we “relat[e] to one another as free and equal agents,” 79 Id. at 1416. where “free and equal” means, of course, “substantively, not merely formally, free and equal.” 80 Id. at 1417. One can see, then, why I glean from their text that private law is supposed to answer to these specific values—substantive freedom and equality—only.

Yet this parsimony with value may not extend to other areas of the law, or to public policy in general. Apparently there are also various “public goals” 81 Id. at 1410. or “public ends” 82 Id. at 1429. that may properly be pursued by pub­lic law. Dagan and Dorfman do not clarify whether they are all supposed to be goals relating to freedom and equality, differing from those of pri­vate law merely by their lack of “relational form,” or whether acceptable “public goals” might include the service of further, and possibly unrelated, values. Certainly “social welfare” is mentioned more than once 83 Id. at 1412, 1435. as figuring among “any number of external good causes” 84 Id. at 1412. that public law might orient itself toward (and that private law might happen to serve but is not to orient itself toward). One has the impression, although the point is not spelled out, that this “social welfare” is not held to be reducible to freedom or equality or any combination of the two. But one can certainly imagine a view according to which our “social wel­fare” is maximized if and only if we have, between us, as much substan­tive freedom and equality as can be had. If that is what Dagan and Dorfman think would count as maximizing social welfare, and if maximizing social welfare is their only live example of a “public goal,” then maybe they do after all subscribe to position (i) or (ii) on the origi­nal list of possibilities.

But I am loath to land them with such an implausible view and more inclined to think that they are listing “social welfare” as a further value in its own right. The problem is that Dagan and Dorfman provide no explanation of what “social welfare” might be such that it might qualify as a value in its own right. It sounds like an artifice of public policy technicians, who condescend to save us, or to save those with authority over us, from the need to confront value in all of its irreducibly diverse and tragically inconvenient reality. It seems, then, as if Dagan and Dorfman, retreating back into the safety of their private-law citadel, are largely abandoning public law to the hostile “critics” outside, not caring much about its fate, even subtly inviting its new captors to make an example of it by submitting it to their notorious “aggregat[ion]” 85 Id. at 1409. of “prefer­ences” torture. 86 Id. at 1442. Do Dagan and Dorfman really want to give the technicians prowling at the gate the gift of a ruling that people’s prefer­ences, no matter whether they be good or bad, really are “considera­tions”? 87 Id. Do they really want to rescue private law from such barbarity only at the price of condemning the rest of the law to it?

What we are detecting here is a deficiency in Dagan and Dorfman’s grasp of the main point of law, meaning not just private law, and not just public law, but all law. The main point of all law is to help people to do the things that they ought to be doing anyway, quite apart from the law. When legal norms are successful in helping people to do what they ought to be doing anyway, those legal norms are also capable of changing, by rendering more determinate, what people ought to be doing. Even when they change what ought to be done, however, they are to be judged, pri­marily, on their ability to get people to do it. What law exists to do is to help those who are subject to it improve the things that they do. Which things, exactly? A partial list was already provided just a few paragraphs ago. The law exists to help people avoid wronging each other, to have healthy relationships, to avoid wasting their lives and destroying their self-respect, to cultivate their virtues, tastes, and skills, to overcome their limitations, and so forth.

These, and others like them, are the main “public goals” of the law. Notice that “avoid wronging each other” is already included on the list. Wronging is analytically something to be avoided, and we all have reason to help people steer clear of it (by talking them out of it, or distracting them, or frustrating them, or standing in their way, or disabling them, or whatever works). 88 I am subscribing here to the classical view according to which a reason to φ is also a reason to do whatever is sufficient to φ, whether or not it is also necessary. That it will put an end to my cold is a reason to blow up the world. Necessity, like proportionality, comes in only in the face of an objection. For a defense, see generally Anthony Kenny, Practical Inference, 26 Analysis 65 (1966). The law is no exception. The main questions for the law, before it intervenes, are much the same as the main questions for you or me before we intervene. Is there any chance that the wrong still can be prevented or mitigated or curtailed? Will it be productive or coun­terproductive if the law is the one to intervene, or to attempt an interven­tion? If several possible modes of intervention by the law would be productive, which would be most productive? Would the most productive also be proportionate? (Killing the wrongdoer: usually not.) Would the most productive make sufficient allowance, in particular, for the value of freedom? Would intervening be too oppressive of the wrongdoer, too judgmental, too intolerant, too intrusive? And would it, not to be forgot­ten, be too much of a usurpation of the freedom of the rightholder? Possibly, although not necessarily, the rightholder’s freedom was already relevant to what made the wrongdoer’s act a wrong against her (suppose it is kidnapping or a discriminatory refusal of entry or censorship of her speech or breach of contract). So perhaps her freedom has been counted once already. But even if it has been, a third-party intervention to prevent the commission of the wrong, especially if the third party is the law, poses new threats to her freedom beyond those posed by the wrong, and possibly even worse than those posed by the wrong. These too must be counted.

Here the loose relationality of private law is playing its part in a per­fectly typical “public goal.” How I just presented it perhaps made you think of a legal intervention in the form of some provision for private-law litigation. But there is no reason to think that the loose relationality in question is restricted to private law. People have, depending on the legal system, not only their contractual rights and property rights and copy­rights and so on but also their human rights and constitutional rights and civil rights and charter rights. These rights are relational in just the same way that private law rights are, even though, in many jurisdictions, they can be upheld only against officials acting in their official capacity, and therefore only through the (usually) distinct mechanisms of public law. 89 Curiously, Dorfman, writing alone, points out these very facts. See Avihay Dorfman, Private Law Exceptionalism? Part I: A Basic Difficulty with the Structural Arguments from Bipolarity and Civil Recourse, 35 Law & Phil. 165, 184 (2016) (“It may be more accurate to say . . . that ‘the principle of civil recourse’ equally applies to interactions among private individuals, which is the case of private law, and to some of the interactions between public officials and private individuals, which is the case of constitutional rights law.”). Apropos of those mechanisms, Dagan and Dorfman say that public law “governs our interactions as patients of the welfare state or as citizens of a democracy.” 90 Dagan & Dorfman, supra note 1, at 1397. But notice that there is a tension in that sentence already. Are we truly patients? Or are we, rather, (inter)agents? There is some truth in both characterizations. When we are rightholders we are sometimes patients (something was done to us without our participation) and sometimes interagents (something was done to us with our participa­tion). But when we are dutybearers, potential wrongdoers, we are always agents. And the law, be it public or private, addresses us only in that agential capacity. Its main point, its overarching “public goal,” is to alter what we do so that we do better, or righter—and, when rightholders are involved, so that we do better, or righter, by others.

Dagan and Dorfman may complain that this argument misses the point here by focusing on the similarities between public law and private law at the point of litigation. They warn against placing too much empha­sis, in thinking about the distinctiveness of private law, upon “the specific legal mechanisms for addressing deviations from this ideal, be they the familiar one-to-one litigation or otherwise.” 91 Id. at 1413. Presumably they would say that, likewise, when they are thinking about public law, writs of certiorari and habeas corpus and the like are not what they have in mind. They have in mind something more like “public regulation” 92 Id. at 1430–31. : everything from the income tax code to the licensing system for private security guards to the work of the competition authorities to the regime for protection against disclosure of personal data. In England and Wales, most of this belongs, strictly speaking, to the criminal law (although parts of it, espe­cially in the regulation of labor and employment, operate via private law or via what might be called private-law-lite). 93 I am not sure whether Dagan and Dorfman agree with my parenthetical qualifica­tion. I find their remarks about statutory antidiscrimination law, which I think of as private-law-lite, do not give a totally clear impression of how they regard it. See id. at 1442. So the legal importance of failing to provide a correct accounting for tax purposes, of not being licensed for the security work that one undertakes, of not obtaining clear­ance for one’s hostile takeover, or of not registering one’s storage of per­sonal data, and so on, is that each of these omissions opens the way, subject to certain further conditions, for a criminal liability in the end. It is misleading to think of any of this as public law, except insofar as the public officials involved are sometimes open to collateral challenge through judicial review or similar means. If the differences between criminal law and private law are Dagan and Dorfman’s main subject matter, it would have been better if they had said so. Be that as it may, the difference between the two subject matters is not as they imagine it to be.

Criminal law, like public law, is in a way an elaborate adaptation of private law, at least across a wide range of cases. A significant part of its raison d’être, at least in these cases, is much as Nils Christie famously explained in his classic anti-criminal-law writings of the 1970s. It is to “steal” the “conflict” from the rightholder. 94 Nils Christie, Conflicts as Property, 17 Brit. J. Criminology 1, 4 (1977). As his choice of words sug­gests, Christie tends to regard that as always a negative, but often enough, it is better regarded as a positive. Often enough, the freedom of the rightholder to tackle his own grievances in his own way does not count in favor of his being left to his own devices to do so, let alone in favor of his being assisted by the law to do so, such a dreadful hash would he make of it even if he had the law’s help. 95 I explored one set of errors that would warrant allowing the criminal law to take over in John Gardner, Offences and Defences 213–238 (2007). These were errors of vindictiveness. A different set of errors arise from vulnerability: The rightholder cannot reasonably be expected to stand up to the wrongdoer. (Remember: The freedom we hope to serve is only the freedom to engage in worthwhile pursuits.)

Whether one favors Christie’s verdict on the “stealing” of “conflict” or mine, however, there is little reason to think that the main “public goal” involved is any different. So, yes, “criminal law should indeed be understood to extend, and even bolster, the force of private law” 96 Dagan & Dorfman, supra note 1, at 1411. over a wide range of cases. In that wide range of cases, it shares private law’s public goal. There is no reason to hesitate in using the expression “pub­lic goal” in connection with private law, once one realizes the obvious: that protecting people’s rights by preventing and mitigating other peo­ple’s wrongs against them is a “garden-variety” public goal, 97 The idea was most famously developed in Amartya Sen, Rights and Agency, 11 Phil. & Pub. Aff. 3, 5 (1981). and that private law is a “garden variety” way of serving it, of which public law and criminal law can each be seen as, in some ways, a specialized develop­ment or extension. Therefore, contra Dagan and Dorfman, there is no reason to shy away from

[The] basic view . . . that “[t]here is work to be done and it ought to be done in the best possible way,” with the choice between private or public agents (or private or public law) a “pragmatic” one that “depends on a comparison between the expected efficacy” of these possible agents “in performing the job.” 98 Dagan & Dorfman, supra note 1, at 1409 (quoting Alon Harel, Public and Private Law, in The Oxford Handbook of Criminal Law 1040, 1051 (Markus D. Dubber & Tatjana Hörnle eds., 2014)).

In resisting such “pragmatism,” Dagan and Dorfman are quoting, and agreeing with, Alon Harel. 99 Alon Harel, Public and Private Law, in The Oxford Handbook of Criminal Law 1040, 1051 (Markus D. Dubber & Tatjana Hörnle eds., 2014). As I replied to Harel on a previous occa­sion: There is nothing to fear in seeing the problem as that of who is best suited to “performing the job.” Working out what is the job—now that is where the action is. 100 See John Gardner, The Evil of Privatization 4 (June 20, 2014) (unpublished manuscript), http://ssrn.com/abstract=2460655 (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (arguing privatization entails “the creeping transformation of our political system and public culture from one of democratic oversight to one of plutocratic oversight”). For further discussion, see W.A. Edmundson, The Zeal of Our Age, Jotwell (Jan. 3, 2017), http://juris.jotwell.com/the-zeal-of-our-age/ [http://perma.cc/7S9X-XPX7] (questioning whether public or private actors can provide a given good or service more efficiently).

Private law is a “garden-variety” way, arguably the most “garden-variety” way, of “performing the job” of helping people to avoid and miti­gate their wrongs against other people, thereby protecting the rights of those other people. That job, this Response has argued, is one that pri­vate law performs (a) instrumentally, (b) more or less dispensably, and often (c) only with the loose kind of relationality that is entailed by the mere fact that we are dealing with rightholders and wrongs committed against them. It needs to do so, moreover, (d) with due regard to “core liberal values” but without needing to be exclusively fixated with them. That being so, private law does not seem to have any, let alone all, of the four main differentia that Dagan and Dorfman claim for it. Its moral dis­tinctiveness, such as it is, resides elsewhere.